|
The Antinomies of Antonio
Gramsci
THE ANTINOMIES OF
ANTONIO GRAMSCI
Perry Anderson
First published by Verso 2017
© Perry Anderson 2017
Translation of Athos Lisa’s report © Eleanor Chiari 2017
All rights reserved
The moral rights of the authors have been asserted
1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 2
Verso
UK: 6 Meard Street, London W1F 0EG
US: 20 Jay Street, Suite 1010, Brooklyn, NY 11201
versobooks.com
Verso is the imprint of New Left Books
ISBN-13: 978-1-78663-372-9
ISBN-13: 978-1-78663-375-0 (US EBK)
ISBN-13: 978-1-78664-374-3 (UK EBK)
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from
the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication
Data
A catalog record for this book is available from the
Library of Congress
Typeset in Minion Pro by MJ & N Gavan, Truro,
Cornwall
Printed in the US by Maple Press
CONTENTS
Preface
1.Alteration
2.Variants
3.Asymmetry
4.Contexts
5.Implications
Annexe: Athos Lisa’s Report
Notes
Index
PREFACE
No Italian thinker enjoys a greater fame today than
Antonio Gramsci. If academic citations and internet references
are any guide, he is more influential than Machiavelli. The
bibliography of articles and books about him now runs to some
20,000 items. Amid this avalanche, is any compass possible? The Prison
Notebooksfirst became available, thematically pre-packaged
and politically expurgated, in Italy in the later 1940s. The
first extensive translation from them into any language came in
the early 1970s, with Selections in English produced by
Quintin Hoare and Geoffrey Nowell Smith, giving them a global
readership in what is still probably the most widely consulted
single version of his writings. Some four decades later, the
history of their worldwide reception is itself a scholarly
topic, covering a vast span of usages.1The scale of
this appropriation, in an epoch so unlike that in which Gramsci
lived and thought, has owed much to two features of his legacy
that set it apart from that of any other revolutionary of his
time.
The first was its multidimensionality. The range of
topics covered in the Prison Notebooks—the history of
leading European states; the structure of their ruling classes;
the character of their dominion over the ruled; the function and
variation of intellectuals; the experience of workers and the
outlook of peasants; the relations between state and civil
society; the latest forms of production and consumption;
questions of philosophy and education; the interconnexions
between traditional or avant-garde and popular or folkloric
culture; the construction of nations and the survival of
religions; and, not least, the ways and means of passing beyond
capitalism and sustaining socialism—had, and has, no equal in
the theoretical literature of the left. The range was not only
topical but spatial, since Italy combined an advanced capitalist
industry in the North with an archaic pre-capitalist society in
the South, and the Notebooks came from a direct
experience of both, capable in another time of speaking to First
and Third World readers alike. There was a lot to choose from.
The second magnetic attraction of this writing lay
in its fragmentation. In prison, Gramsci’s notes were laconic,
exploratory jottings for works he was never able to compose in
freedom. That made them, as David Forgacs would point out,
suggestive rather than conclusive, inviting imaginative
reconstruction after his death, into one kind of totalisation or
another.2 Less binding than a finished theory, they
were the more appealing to interpreters of every sort—a score
inviting improvisation. In that attraction lay, inevitably, also
a temptation. What were the limits beyond which the score itself
was broken? That was one basic question the essay below set out
to address. At this date, some explanation of its origins, aims
and reception is needed. As a study of central political
concepts in Gramsci, it followed the reception of his work in
the New Left Review of the early sixties, historically
the first sustained attempt to make use of it outside his
homeland. Concerned with analysis of the past and present of
British society, this body of writing set out to put Gramsci’s
ideas to work more than to expound them. But soon afterwards,
the journal began to publish translations and presentations of
the canon of a Western Marxism that had developed in Europe
outside the Soviet Union after the October Revolution, still
vital—Lukács, Sartre, Adorno, Althusser were all active—at the
time, with the aim of explicating and assessing its major
thinkers.3 Gramsci occupied a central place in this
line. A product of that collective project was an essay that I
published in 1974 attempting to resume the tradition, Considerations
on Western Marxism.
A year later the first critical edition of the
notebooks Gramsci composed in prison appeared in Italy, the
fruit of years of meticulous work by Valentino Gerratana, a
Communist scholar of outstanding sobriety and dignity. With this
in hand, in late 1976 I wrote the text that ensues. The
intention of ‘Antinomies’ was twofold, philological and
historical: to look closely at the usage of central concepts in
the Prison Notebooks, in a way that had not been done
before, and to reconstruct the political contexts in which they
originated and to which their meanings referred. The effect of
doing so was, equally, twofold: to show the oscillations and
contradictions in even, or perhaps particularly, the most
striking and original themes of the Notebooks, with the
intelligible reasons for these; and to demonstrate that,
politically speaking, Gramsci was a revolutionary of Leninist
stamp, whose strategic thought could only be understood within
the parameters of the Third International and its debates.
Conceived as a sequel to Considerations,
‘Antinomies’ was composed in late 1976, and came out in New
Left Review at the beginning of 1977. The following year it
was published as a book in Italy under the title Ambiguità di
Gramsci. There the Italian Communist Party had for some time
declared that the way forward for the party and the country lay
in a Historic Compromise with Christian Democracy, and in the
summer of 1976 had achieved its highest ever level of electoral
support, with over a third of the vote. In the wake of this
success it was now backing a government of ‘National Solidarity’
led by Giulio Andreotti. This was a turn that in different ways
had its counterpart in most of the Communist parties of Western
Europe. Theorised as Eurocommunism by the Spanish party leader
Santiago Carrillo, then helping to restore the Bourbon monarchy
in Madrid, it was reproduced in its fashion by the Communist
party in France, where the new doctrine had early adepts. Common
to all variants was rejection of the principles on which the
Third International had been founded, and commitment
henceforward to gradual parliamentary reforms as the West
European path to socialism; the Italian version adding a
declaration of loyalty to NATO. In these conditions, the image
of Gramsci—for the PCI, a national icon who could not be
casually abandoned—had to be adjusted to the needs of the time,
as a far-sighted precursor of the party’s conversion to
peaceful, incremental progress towards more advanced forms of
democracy.
The Italian Socialist Party, under its new leader
Bettino Craxi, did not, however, intend to let itself be
marginalised by the Historic Compromise, and soon showed its
ability to wrong-foot its larger rival. An early sign was the
appearance in the autumn of 1976 of four articles in its monthly
journal Mondoperaio by leading intellectuals—two
historians, Massimo Salvadori and Ernesto Galli della Loggia,
and two philosophers, Norberto Bobbio and Lucio
Colletti—congratulating the PCI on its new outlook, but calling
on it to abandon the pretence that this had anything to do with
Gramsci, who had been a dedicated revolutionary committed to the
overthrow of the very liberal democracy to which the PCI had now
at last rallied, as it became—a development which was entirely
positive—for all practical purposes a reformist party in the
tradition of Kautsky and European social democracy.4 Put
on the defensive, the PCI—which had been organising its own
discussion to explain how its current positions were a creative
development of the heritage of Gramsci—at first responded
testily, then mindful of the need for national solidarity, more
temperately but for the most part lamely, in early 1977. These
exchanges overlapped with the appearance of ‘Antinomies’ in New
Left Review. But not following the Italian political scene
closely enough at that point, I was unaware of them.
Later that year, to commemorate the fortieth
anniversary of Gramsci’s death, the PCI organised its
largest-ever conference on his thought. Held in Florence, and
attended by numerous foreign participants, it marked, in the
words of the richest history of the reception of Gramsci in
Italy, the apogee of his influence in the public life of the
country. But, as the same account added, also the moment of its
crisis.5 For this was also the year of the widespread
student and youth revolt against the Historic Compromise and all
that it stood for, which became the ‘Autonomia’. In February,
the head of the PCI’s trade union wing, who had told workers
they must make economic sacrifices to prop up the National
Solidarity government, was driven off the campus of Rome
University amid angry scenes, and by the autumn Bologna was the
stage of a virtual uprising. The Autonomia would fade, but the
PCI never recovered from the alienation its connubium with
Christian Democracy caused in the most politicised spirits of
the younger generation. By the end of 1978 the failure of the
Historic Compromise even on its own terms—the DC had taken
Communist votes and yielded nothing in return—was obvious, and
the PCI was duly punished at the elections the following year,
beginning its slow descent towards dissolution.
The publication of Ambiguità di Gramsci in
the spring of 1978 thus came at a juncture of continuing
insistence by the PCI that its support for National Solidarity
was thoroughly Gramscian, and a revolt against both the
political line and the whole culture of the PCI by radical
forces of a new generation to the left of it. For the latter,
Gramsci was an irrelevance. For the former, any reminder of his
connexion with Bolshevism could only be an embarrassment to the
pursuit of a marriage with Christian Democracy. Logically, the
book was ignored by the one and dismissed by the other.6
Some six years later, however—by this time the
Historic Compromise had been abandoned, though it was never
repudiated—a reply was forthcoming. L’officina gramsciana marked
the debut of a party intellectual with a future, Gianni
Francioni. Proposing a reconstruction of the Prison Notebooks based
on an attempt to determine as far as possible the precise
chronological sequence of their composition, its aim was
twofold: to dismantle the order of the critical edition produced
by Gerratana, and to refute ‘Antinomies’, an exercise to which
the latter part of the book was dedicated.7 So far as
the first went, the battery of tables and charts designed to
establish the novelty and importance of Francioni’s findings
left Gerratana politely unpersuaded.8 Lacking any
reference to the trajectory of the actual conditions, physical
and moral, in which Gramsci had to write in prison, the result
says much less about the history of his composition than the
acute and moving account of it by another scholar, Raul
Mordenti, in the following decade.9
As to Francioni’s other aim, the guiding principles
behind his argument were affirmation of the essential coherence
of Gramsci’s conceptual apparatus, and abstraction of it from
any significant historical context; the first revolving around
reiteration of the claim earlier advanced by a French stalwart
of Eurocommunism, Christine Buci-Glucksmann, that contradictions
in Gramsci’s handling of the terms ‘state’ and ‘civil society’
disappeared once it was realised that he arrived at the notion
of an ‘enlarged’ or ‘integral’ state encompassing both. The
second involved a taboo on all evidence, however plain, that
Gramsci’s political outlook had by then virtually nothing in
common with what the PCI had become. Chronological quibbles
added little to the case.10 As an enterprise in local
apologetics, L’officina gramsciana was soon overtaken by
events, as the party lurched towards its end. Three years later,
on the fiftieth anniversary of Gramsci’s death in 1987, Colletti
could remark with relief that the left in Italy was now
universally reformist, but Gramsci had never been, and the party
had therefore rightly taken an all but irreversible distance
from him. Within the PCI, no less an authority than Aldo
Schiavone, director of the Gramsci Institute itself, concurred:
in the overall politics of the party, he declared, not a single
Gramscian idea was left.11 Nor, it might be said, any
other idea of moment in those who led it to extinction soon
afterwards.
In Italy, the disappearance of the PCI has not meant
loss of public interest in its greatest thinker. Too many
careers, institutional or academic, remained invested in his
person and work for the Gramsci industry in the country to close
down along with the party that had given rise to it. Across the
nineties and into the new century an indefatigable flow of
exegesis has continued, in a philology now detached from
current—if not always past—politics, culminating in the
inception of an Edizione Nazionale of Gramsci’s opera omnia,
‘under the High Patronage of the President of the Republic’, in
2007. Planned to total some nineteen volumes, a decade later
just three have so far appeared, two of them simply translations
from other writers by Gramsci, a rate at which the project could
expect completion around 2070. Responsibility for volumes to
contain in due course the Prison Notebooks has been
entrusted to Francioni, fulfilling his ambition of supplanting
the work of Gerratana, a scholar of an older style of integrity
cold-shouldered by the legatees of his party.12 Misgivings
about the enterprise have been expressed by scholars attached to
the memory of Gramsci in less marmoreal mode. Francioni’s
proposed rearrangements of the Notebooks have come under
fire as arbitrary personal decisions, serving in one
case—already on display—a concealed political intent with no
philological foundation; while the monumental character of a
National Edition, product of a decree of the Ministry of
Culture, has prompted fears even among otherwise sympathetic
critics that its effect risks official mummification of Gramsci.13
The most conspicuous other body of literature on
Gramsci in Italy has been of an entirely different tenor, this
one concerned—in recent times, to virtual paroxysm—with
biographical questions about his personal life and political
fate. These have surfaced as what was once tight party control
of archives held in Rome has loosened, if still selectively, and
what were formerly closed dossiers in Moscow have opened, if
incompletely. New documentary evidence has come to light about
the Russian family into which he married, the roles of Piero
Sraffa and his sister-in-law Tatiana Schucht in his
communications with the party while in prison, the actions taken
towards him by the PCI and the Comintern in those years, the
fate of his notebooks after his death, and much else. The
copious literature all this has produced contains much of
interest. But it has been persistently vitiated by two opposite
instrumental motives.14 Communism may have
disappeared in Italy, but anti-communism has not: much of this
biographical production serves simply as a stick with which to
beat the PCI or Togliatti, not matter how long the party has
been, politically speaking, a chien crevé. Conversely,
post-communism has bent every effort to defend its
transformation by presenting a new image of Gramsci as not just
foreshadowing, but actually already embodying the peace it has
made with capitalism in general, and the American world order in
particular.15Sensation, speculation, and manipulation
have marked treatments on both sides. The most extravagant
constructions, culminating in claims that Gramsci was a liberal
democrat who broke with communism in prison, that Togliatti not
only connived at his continued imprisonment, but after his death
suppressed or destroyed a missing notebook that no doubt
recorded his conversion to Western values, have come from the
anti-communist side, provoking in reply a questionnaire
assembling some twenty indignant or dismissive post-communist
responses.16 The furore, played out in the media, is
no advertisement for the present state of intellectual life in
Italy.
Abroad, the most substantial study of the Prison
Notebooks to appear in recent years has been Peter Thomas’s
work The Gramscian Moment, which came out in 2009. Nearly
half of this is devoted to refutation of ‘Antinomies’, along
lines inspired by Francioni, and following him, the authority of
Buci-Glucksmann.17 The centrepiece of the exercise is
once more the argument, that Gramsci’s variant usages of ‘state’
and ‘civil society’ are perfectly consistent with each other,
derived from an ‘integral’ conception of the state including
both. Thomas traces such an understanding of the state back to
Hegel, and argues that in his development of this notion—not in
his concern with hegemony—lay Gramsci’s real originality. For
Anglophone readers, The Gramscian Moment thus performs
the service of introducing what Thomas describes as the
philological acquisitions of ‘the most recent season of
Gramscian scholarship’ on an expanded scale.18 There
is, it is true, an element of oddity in the performance.
Motivating the length of his critique of ‘Antinomies’, Thomas
maintains that ‘it is the most well-known and influential of all
studies of Gramsci in English’, which ‘won wide assent’ as
‘representative of a more general received image of Gramsci’,
acting indeed as a veritable ‘touchstone’ in the field.19 The
most cursory glance at the extant literature, overwhelmingly
dominated by approaches close in spirit to that of Thomas
himself, suffices to dispel any such idea.
More significant than this quirk is the apolitical
cast of a work whose declared aim is to ‘repropose a
distinctively Marxist philosophical research programme’.20Across
four hundred and fifty pages on Gramsci, there is scarcely one
concrete reference to what is known of his politics, let alone
to the politics of his reception, in Italy or elsewhere—not a
single mention of Athos Lisa’s report on Gramsci’s political
lectures in prison, inconvenient from so many points of view.
Though in this too following in the footsteps of Francioni, the
reasons for such silence are plainly not the same, since Thomas
is above suspicion of any sympathy with the Historic Compromise,
or what preceded and followed it. What might explain it? The
answer, in all probability, lies in dependence on the milieu of
post-communist scholars in Italy whose labours The Gramscian
Moment extols, and whose sensibilities any more robust or
explicit political standpoint would offend.21 It
would be a mistake, however, to narrow this tacit connexion to a
mere question of politesse. A shared premise is visibly
at work, one that is widespread in intellectual history at
large, beyond the study of Gramsci. This is the assumption—so
common as to be virtually automatic—that the thought of any
great mind must be as coherent as it is august, and that the
highest task of commentary on it is to demonstrate its
fundamental underlying unity. The reality is just the opposite:
the thought of a genuinely original mind will typically
exhibit—not randomly but intelligibly—significant structural
contradictions, inseparable from its creativity, on which
attempts to impose or extract an artificial homogeneity can only
end in simplification and distortion. Conspicuous examples are
the fate of three of the most powerful political thinkers of the
early modern period, Machiavelli, Hobbes and Rousseau, all of
whose oeuvres are riven by central contradictions, each
regularly victim of misguided efforts to apply Davidson’s
principle of charity to them. In the grip of this eminently
conventional assumption, the aim of any well-meaning study of
Gramsci becomes a demonstration of its higher unity, producing
more or less ingenious exercises in what ancient and mediaeval
wisdom termed ‘saving the appearances’.22Thomas’s
book is not to be especially blamed for an error that is so
general, nor reduced to it, since the better part of the work is
concerned with the more strictly philosophical side of the Prison
Notebooks.
In the case of Gramsci, there is an obvious contrast
between what Gramsci himself believed and what became standard
usages of his texts. Setting aside the record of manipulations
by officialdom, this was not purely a product of distortion by
subsequent interpreters. It was possible because Gramsci’s
intellectual explorations contain many divergent emphases, which
he was under little pressure to reconcile or summarise. They do
not aim at the construction of a system: there is an evident
lack of anxiety about the chance of contradictions, as well as a
series of circumlocutions and omissions due to censorship.
Moreover, within the form of jotted enquiry that he chose, it is
clear that what mainly interested Gramsci was terrain uncharted
by historical materialism—questions that the Marxist tradition
had said little about, taking much of what it did say for
granted. The result of these two circumstances—the unbinding
character of the mosaic, exploratory form, and the unspoken
nature of certain background assumptions—was a composition that
dispenses with criteria of expository coherence and protocols of
reference to the Comintern canon. If Gramsci had ever been able
to work the materials of the Quaderni up for publication,
he would certainly have attended to these. We can say this with
confidence from his pre-prison writings alone. The form, not
unlike that of a commonplace book, that Gramsci’s reflections
took in prison rendered it quite possible to develop ideas in
not always consistent directions, sometimes leaving a logical
route to conclusions at variance with what we know on other
grounds he believed. To say, as I did, that on such occasions
Gramsci ‘lost his way’, was overly dramatic, in keeping with a
rhetorical strand in the text as a whole. But that Gramsci
himself was well aware of the provisional and potentially
fallible character of his reflections is clear. As he wrote:
‘The notes contained in this notebook, as in the others, were
jotted down as quick prompts pro memoria. They are all to
be punctiliously revised and checked, since they certainly
contain imprecisions, false connexions, anachronisms. Written
without access to books to which they refer, it is possible that
after checking, they should be radically corrected, as the very
opposite of what they say proves true.’23
That my essay was open to a different sort of
criticism became clear to me on reading Eric Hobsbawm’s
reflections on Gramsci, a few months after ‘Antinomies’ appeared
in NLR. In March 1977 he gave a short paper to a conference on
Gramsci in London, published in Marxism Today in July,
which he expanded into an address to the large fortieth
anniversary conference organised by the PCI in Florence in
December, subsequently published in 1982.24 A quarter
of a century later, the initial London version became a chapter
in his collection of writings on Marxism, How to Change the
World, which appeared in 2011.25 But the more
developed version delivered in Florence remains essential
reading. In either variant, within the space of scarcely more
than a dozen pages, Hobsbawm produced the best general
characterisation of Gramsci as a revolutionary thinker that has
yet been written, at a succinct depth without equal in the
literature.
Gramsci’s key originality, he argued, lay in the way
in which he theorised problems both of revolutionary strategy
for the conquest of power from capital, and of the construction
of a society beyond capital, in a common conceptual framework
based on his idea of hegemony. It was a mistake to stress only
the first, without giving due weight to the second. Gramsci was
fond of military metaphors, but never a prisoner of them, since
‘for a soldier war is not peace, even if it is the continuation
of politics by other means and victory is, professionally
speaking, an end in itself’, whereas for Gramsci ‘the struggle
to overthrow capitalism and build socialism is essentially a
continuum, in which the actual transfer of power is only one
moment’.26 It followed that ‘the basic problem of
hegemony is not how revolutionaries come to power, though
this question is very important. It is how they come to be
accepted, not only as the politically existing and unavoidable
rulers, but as guides and leaders’.27 Here it was
important to remember that unlike either Marx or Lenin, Gramsci
had in post-war Turin direct experience of work in a mass labour
movement and what it meant to lead one, which gave him a much
greater sense of the cultural transformations required, absent
international war, to overturn the existing order and to build a
new society that would last. Socialism meant not just
socialisation of production, fundamental though that was, but
socialisation in the sociological sense of the word, of people
into new human relationships and structures of genuinely popular
rule, dissolving the barriers between state and civil society.
The hegemony that had to be won not just before and during, but
after a revolution, could only be achieved by active mass
participation and consensual education, ‘the school of a new
consciousness, a fuller humanity for the socialist future’.28 In
Russia, the dangers of a bureaucratism crushing any such
prospect were plainly one of his preoccupations in prison.
This was a vision, Hobsbawm remarked, based on a
general theory of politics of a kind that Marxism had always
lacked, linking Gramsci to Machiavelli as thinkers of the
foundation and transformation of societies. Distinctive of
Gramsci’s conception, however, was his understanding that there
is more to politics than power—that societies are not just
structures of economic domination or political force, but
possess a certain cultural cohesion even when riven by class
antagonisms. In modern conditions, that meant the nation was
always a critical arena of struggles between classes. Typically,
identification of the nation with the state and civil society of
the rulers was the strongest element in their hegemony, and
successful challenges to it a characteristic achievement of a
victorious revolution.
Strategically, a war of position had been imposed on
the working class in Europe in the wake of its defeats after the
First World War and the isolation of the Soviet Union. But it
was no absolute principle, a war of movement remaining open if
circumstances changed. Nor, on the other hand, was it simply a
temporary requirement in the West, but rather a necessary
component of any hard revolutionary fight, everywhere in the
world. Gramsci was neither any sort of gradualist nor a
Eurocommunist ante diem, Hobsbawm told his Italian
listeners. In prison, he was writing in a period of bitter
working class defeats by fascism in Central and Eastern Europe,
and seeking a way out of the impasse of the Third International
at the time. But unlike any of its other leaders, he saw that
defeat did not leave victors and vanquished unchanged, and
‘might produce a much more dangerous long-term weakening of the
forces of progress, by means of what he called a “passive
revolution”. On the one hand, the ruling class might grant
certain demands to forestall and avoid revolution, on the other,
the revolutionary movement might find itself in practice (though
not necessarily in theory) accepting its impotence and might be
eroded and politically integrated into the system’.29 Pointed
words, spoken in London, which Hobsbawm spared his audience in
Florence.
Gramsci was not to be judged against present or past
policies of the post-war PCI. Nor was he to be taken as an
unquestioned authority. His observations on the Soviet regime in
the time of Stalin were overly optimistic, and the remedies
against it at which he hinted undoubtedly insufficient. The
importance he attached to the role of intellectuals in the
workers’ movement and in history at large was not, as it stood,
really convincing. To express such disagreements was to follow
the example he set. Hobsbawm ended his address in Florence: ‘We
are fortunate enough to be able to continue his labours. I hope
we shall do so with as much independence as he did’.30
No more compelling overview of Gramsci’s thought in
prison has been written. At its altitude, textual scrutiny of
any detail was supernumerary. ‘Antinomies’ moved at a much
closer level to the Prison Notebooks, with a more limited
focus: essentially, the ways in which ‘hegemony’ functions in
them, and its interconnexions with the task Gramsci set himself
of developing a strategy for revolution in the West, as distinct
from that which had been successful in Russia. To understand
these, it argued, a purely internal reconstruction of his
concepts was not enough: they had to be situated in a lattice of
intense debates within and beyond the international
revolutionary movement of the time, which had not been looked at
before. No claim was made that this line of enquiry exhausted
Gramsci’s intellectual or political importance. His larger
conception of politics, of the nation, of intellectuals, of
passive revolution—all topics touched on by Hobsbawm—as of
Americanism and Fordism, not to speak of philosophy, common
sense, popular culture and much else besides, lay outside its
brief; their absence was no reproach to it. Exclusion of the
problem of stabilizing a post-revolutionary regime was another
matter. That was certainly to abridge in a quite fundamental way
Gramsci’s understanding of, and preoccupation with, hegemony. In
London, Hobsbawm observed: ‘we are talking here about two different sets
of problems: strategy and the nature of socialist society.
Gramsci tried to get to grips with both, though some
commentators [adding in Florence, ‘abroad’] seem to me to have
concentrated excessively on only one of them, namely the
strategic’.31 Given the lack at that date of any
serious critical analysis of Gramsci’s strategic thinking, it
would have been difficult to measure an excess of it. But
one-sided the focus of ‘Antinomies’ was, and remains. Hobsbawm’s
tacit rebuke was justified, and his reminder of the centrality
for Gramsci of post-revolutionary issues a necessary corrective.
In Italy, it was Sebastiano Timpanaro who made the same
observation to me when it appeared there.
My explanation of the apparent casualness of
Gramsci’s treatment of the problematic of Niederwerfung in
his notebooks —that he just took the principle of an ‘overthrow’
for granted, given its centrality to the formation of the Third
International, and so of the detachment of it which he had led,
and was anyway not something on which he could dwell under the
eye of the censor in prison—was thus insufficient. For while
Gramsci took the overthrow of the capitalist state to be
indispensable, and conceived it quite classically, there was
also a sense in which he thought that the construction of a
revolutionary bloc before the conquest of power, and the
consolidation of a new communist order after it, were harder and
deeper tasks. From quite early on, he seems to have arrived at
this conviction, derived in part from the rapid collapse of the
Hungarian and Bavarian Communes in 1919, which led him to
reflect how much easier was the apparent destruction of an older
order than the effective construction of a new one; in part from
his contempt for the incendiary rhetoric of Italian Maximalists,
‘who inserted the noun “violence” between every third word in
their speeches’, and thought that revolutionary;32 and
later, of course, in large part from his concern for the fate of
the smychka—the alliance of workers and peasants—in
Russia, and more generally the direction that party rule was
taking after the death of Lenin. Guarding against these dangers,
the principle of hegemony was the connective tissue capable of
unifying the revolutionary process across the divide between
opposite social orders and political regimes.
There I overlooked what Gerratana, alone in his
party, had seen in the seventies. Under pressure from the PSI
symposium in Mondoperaio, the PCI organised its own
seminar on Gramsci in early 1977, at which he delivered the sole
distinguished contribution, that would subsequently appear in
modified form in the papers for the conference at Florence, and
a decade later be distilled into the finest concentrate of
Gramsci’s conception of hegemony, at a level textually closer
than that offered by Hobsbawm, that we possess.33 Linking
two passages in the Notebooks, Gerratana pointed out that
a structural distinction between bourgeois and proletarian
hegemony—which I had argued was missing in Gramsci—could in fact
be found in them. In the first, Gramsci not only illustrated his
famous contrast between domination and direction, the one
directed at adversaries and the other at allies, and the
possibility of the second preceding the first, with the example
of the hegemony of the Moderates over the Action Party in the
Risorgimento, but went on to observe that after the unification
of Italy was achieved, the Moderates continued to exercise a
hegemony whose parliamentary expression was trasformismo—‘that
is, the development of an ever broader ruling class’ by ‘gradual
but continual absorption, with methods of variable efficacy, of
the active elements of allied groups and even of adversaries who
seemed irreconcilable enemies. In this sense political direction
became an aspect of the function of domination, in so far as the
absorption of the elites of enemy groups led to their
decapitation and annihilation for a period that was often very
long’.34 Bourgeois hegemony, in other words, extended
beyond allies to adversaries, direction becoming subsumed in
domination.
Could proletarian hegemony reproduce this figure of
power? It could not, Gerratana argued, for a reason indicated by
Gramsci elsewhere. Bourgeois ideologies were designed to mask
contradictory interests by offering the appearance of a peaceful
reconciliation of them, concealing the exploitation on which the
society of capital was based. They required deception. Marxism,
by contrast, was the exposure of the contradiction between
capital and labour on which bourgeois civilisation rested, and
demanded the truth about both. For it was ‘not an instrument of
the rule of dominant groups to obtain consensus and exercise
hegemony over subaltern classes’, but ‘an expression of these
subaltern classes which want to educate themselves in the art of
government and whose interest is in knowing all the truth, even
when it is harsh, and avoiding not only the (impossible)
deceptions of the class above it, but still more any
self-deceptions’.35 This was a fundamental
difference. It was taken for granted by the established order
that ‘lying is essential to the art of politics, the astute
ability to conceal one’s real opinions and aims, to give out the
opposite of what one wants’, but ‘in mass politics, to speak the
truth is a precise political necessity’, and the kinds of
consent on which each form of hegemony rested were consequently
opposites: ‘passive and indirect’ subordination in one case,
‘direct and active participation’ in the other.36
The difference at work in these passages is, in
effect, deontological—what in the Crocean terms adopted on
occasion by Gramsci could be called ethico-political. They speak
of what the hegemony of the working class should be, without
raising the empirical question of what, on a realistic
historical reckoning, it could be. There, Gramsci had an answer
in the time of the factory councils in Turin, when not for
nothing was his paper entitled L’Ordine Nuovo. The test
of proletarian hegemony was its ability to unleash productive
superior forces, by not only occupying but operating industrial
plants, after banishing managers and capitalists from them. ‘Two
Revolutions’, written in July 1920 between the peaks of labour
insurgency in Northern Italy, April and September of that year,
was explicit: if the revolution had failed in Germany, Austria,
Bavaria, the Ukraine and Hungary, it was because ‘the presence
of external conditions—a communist party, the destruction of the
bourgeois state, highly organised trade-unions and an armed
proletariat—was not enough to compensate for the absence of
another condition’—‘a conscious movement of the proletarian
masses to give substance to their political power with economic
power, and a determination on the part of these proletarian
masses to introduce proletarian order into the factory, to make
the factory the nucleus of the new state’. 37
In the Prison Notebooks, Gramsci continued to
express a belief that the hegemony of the proletariat had to be
anchored in production, but the essential emphasis of his
conception of it had shifted. Hegemony, now repeatedly
associated with superstructures, became preeminently a matter of
cultural ascendancy. Could the working class hope to exercise
that before it won power, as the bourgeoisie had done before it?
The standard readings of Gramsci in Italy and elsewhere held
that this was his suggestion. There is no doubt that many of his
entries left such a construction of them open, and such was my
criticism of them. But his notes contain counter-indications,
the most important of which I noted, even if these still sit
awkwardly amid the general direction of his comments, an example
of the discrepancies inseparable from their form. Twice, the
same adverb delivers the necessary rectification: ‘subaltern
groups always undergo the initiative of dominant groups, even
when they rise up and rebel: only “permanent” victory breaks,
and not immediately, their subordination’—‘only after the
creation of the state is the cultural problem posed in all its
complexity and tends towards a coherent solution’.38
Gerratana, the one cogent critic of Salvadori from
the PCI in 1977, made no secret of his disagreement with party
notables who were already calling on it to ‘go beyond’ hegemony,
arguing firmly for the need to remain faithful to ‘the general
project of a social transformation of universal character’,
rather than a mere reformism ‘satisfied with itself ’.39 Gramsci
was a revolutionary thinker, he reminded those in attendance at
Florence capable of forgetting it. His final thoughts on
hegemony were delivered in Moscow in 1987, on the eve of the end
of the Soviet experience.
*
In the years since, the twin problematics that were
central to Gramsci in his lifetime—the overcoming of capitalism,
the building of socialism—have faded from the horizon. Forces of
production have not burst relations of production; the labour
movement is a shadow of its past; mourned or execrated, the
October Revolution is a distant memory.
In the conjuncture of ‘Antinomies’—this was as true
of Hobsbawm or Gerratana as of myself—we were writing of a
different era: a time when there had recently been the largest
mass strike in history in France, the overthrow of a government
by workers in Britain, continuous outbreaks of revolt in Italy,
the defeat of the United States in Vietnam, and a revolution in
Portugal, where hopes and fears of a social upheaval,
galvanizing Washington and Bonn to vigilance, were still fresh.
It was the last hour of what Lukács, in his tribute to Lenin in
1923, had called the actuality of the revolution. Portugal
features both in ‘Antinomies’ and in Hobsbawm’s rejoinders to
it. On reading the first, Franco Moretti told me, as I have
written elsewhere, that it was a fitting farewell to the
revolutionary Marxist tradition.40 That was not how I
saw it then. But time was on his side, where it has remained.
It was a contemporary and, in those years, friend of
his, Galli della Loggia, who saw more clearly than anyone else
in 1976–7 what lay ahead. Though opposite in their depictions of
Gramsci, he remarked, both sides in the debate set off by
Salvadori had missed his real significance, failing to
understand that his conception of hegemony was not just a
political, but an epochal category. It designated the Weltanschauung of
an entire society, as Hegel had conceived their succession from
one spirit of the age to the next, exemplified in modern times
by the encompassing ideology of bourgeois society in Europe at
its height, which Gramsci believed would be followed by the sway
of a comparable Weltanschauung—the ‘philosophy of
praxis’—to come.
But the society to which industrial capitalism had
given birth had no place for ideologies of this kind. Hegemony
in it could dispense with them; it lay in a set of lifestyles,
conducts, needs, demands, whose origin and end was in the world
of commodities—their production, consumption and distribution.
Mass industrial democracy had no ethos, no directive idea, no
concern with the inner life of the individual, which was
delivered over to the market and the unconscious. Intellectuals,
to whom Gramsci attached such importance, were either entirely
detached from this universe or utterly immersed in it, vectors
of high and low culture that could no longer generate any
synthesis. Its basic value was tolerance, that is, indifference.
Because Italy was still a relatively backward capitalist society
in Gramsci’s time, he could think the Hegelian vision might
continue. He was too Italian, too Southern, to understand that
‘his’ Croce, ‘his’ Vatican, ‘his’ peasants, ‘his’
intellectuals—all the national furniture of his mind—were about
to vanish. The new hegemony would rival in strength that of any
in history. But it would be anthropological, not ideological.
Was it stable? Based on the desires of the individual, it could
only lead to an acute crisis of individuality, whose symptoms
could already be detected in the school and the family. Bobbio
was right: democracy was a road that led no-one knew where. But
it was absurd to pretend nothing had changed.41
The overstatement in this verdict was, no doubt,
itself ideological enough. But that it captured features of the
postmodern landscape of capital that would emerge within a few
years, and is still with us, is incontestable. The passionate
world of ideas and arguments explored below belongs, as Galli
della Loggia saw, to another epoch. That is true, of course, of
all significant political debates of the past, few failing to
repay historical enquiry altogether. How far this particular
past is only of antiquarian, rather than contemporary, interest
is less clear. If capital has seen off any prospect of
revolution in the West, for some time now it has also dealt a
quietus to what was traditionally its alternative. ‘Reforms’,
since the eighties, have typically come to mean the introduction
not of milder but harsher forms of capitalism, not less but more
ruthless styles of exploitation and neglect. In that neoliberal
inversion, the recent fate of social democracy is written.
Viewed world-historically, the difference it has made has not
been great. The welfare state attributed to it exists in
countries where it has never enjoyed significant power—Japan,
Switzerland, Ireland, Canada, even in its fashion the United
States—as well as those in which it has. In favourable
conditions, it has yielded a set of small societies in
Scandinavia markedly more civilised than the bourgeois median,
even if these too are now subject to erosion. The balance sheet
of what was once reformism is not negligible, but it is modest.
Of the revolutionary tradition, that cannot be said. Europe was
largely saved from Nazism by the Red Army, and China today looms
larger in the scales of growth and power than the Soviet Union
ever did. The crimes and disasters, not to speak of the ironies
and reversals, of the communist record are plain. But that it
changed the world as the Second International never did is
equally plain. Not coincidentally, the legacy of its ideas, for
those with any interest in ideas, is much richer. Gramsci alone
is sufficient testimony to that.
*
The Antinomies of Antonio Gramsci appears
together with a companion study, The H-Word, which as I
explain there, germinated from it. There is an overlap between
the two, some findings in this essay requiring a brief rehearsal
in its pendant, which readers coming upon both must excuse. In
the interests of readability, I have lightened the text of some,
though not all, of its excess verbal baggage—rhetoric of the
period—but otherwise left as it stands, arguments unaltered. In
an annexe, I have included for the first time in English the
report on Gramsci in prison written by his fellow prisoner Athos
Lisa, without which no historically truthful account of his
political outlook at the time is possible. Finally, I should
mention what in some respects can be regarded a sequel, ‘The
Heirs of Gramsci’, published in No. 100 of the second series of New
Left Review, as ‘The Antinomies of Antonio Gramsci’ was in
No. 100 of the first. I have drawn on its opening paragraphs for
this preface. The rest can be found in The H-Word, save
for its conclusion.
October 2016
THE
ANTINOMIES OF
ANTONIO GRAMSCI
1
ALTERATION
No Marxist thinker after the classical epoch is so
generally respected in the West as Antonio Gramsci. Nor is any
term so freely or diversely invoked on the left as that of
hegemony, to which he gave currency. Gramsci’s reputation, still
local and marginal outside his native Italy in the early
sixties, has a decade later become a worldwide fame. The homage
due to his enterprise in prison is now—thirty years after the
first publication of his notebooks—finally and fully being paid.
Lack of knowledge, or paucity of discussion, have ceased to be
obstacles to the diffusion of his thought. In principle every
revolutionary socialist, not only in the West—if especially in
the West—can henceforward benefit from Gramsci’s patrimony. Yet
at the same time, the spread of Gramsci’s renown has not to date
been accompanied by any corresponding depth of enquiry into his
work. The very range of the appeals now made to his authority,
from the most contrasted sectors of the left, suggests the
limits of close study or comprehension of his ideas. The price
of so ecumenical an admiration is necessarily ambiguity:
multiple and incompatible interpretations of the themes of the Prison
Notebooks.
There are, of course, good reasons for this. No
Marxist work is so difficult to read accurately and
systematically, because of the peculiar conditions of its
composition. To start with, Gramsci underwent the normal fate of
original theorists, from which neither Marx nor Lenin was
exempt: the necessity of working towards radically new concepts
in an old vocabulary, designed for other purposes and times,
which overlaid and deflected their meaning. Just as Marx had to
think many of his innovations in the language of Hegel or Smith,
Lenin in that of Plekhanov and Kautsky, so Gramsci often had to
produce his concepts within the archaic and inadequate apparatus
of Croce or Machiavelli. This familiar problem, however, is
compounded by the fact that Gramsci wrote in prison, under
atrocious conditions, with a fascist censor scrutinizing
everything that he produced. The involuntary disguise that
inherited language so often imposes on a pioneer was thus
superimposed by a voluntary one which Gramsci assumed to evade
his jailers. The result is a work censored twice over: its
spaces, ellipses, contradictions, disorders, allusions,
repetitions, are the result of this uniquely adverse process of
composition. The reconstruction of the hidden order within these
hieroglyphs remains to be done. This difficult enterprise has
scarcely yet been started. A systematic work of recovery is
needed to discover what Gramsci wrote in the true, obliterated
text of his thought. It is necessary to say this as a warning
against all facile or complacent readings of Gramsci: he is
still largely an unknown author to us.
It has now become urgent, however, to look again,
soberly and comparatively, at the texts that have made Gramsci
most famous. For the great mass Communist Parties of Western
Europe—in Italy, in France, in Spain—are now on the threshold of
a historical experience without precedent for them: the
assumption of governmental office within the framework of
bourgeois-democratic states, without the allegiance to a horizon
of ‘proletarian dictatorship’ beyond them that was once the
touchstone of the Third International. If one political ancestry
is more widely and insistently invoked than any other for the
new perspectives of ‘Eurocommunism’, it is that of Gramsci. It
is not necessary to accredit any apocalyptic vision of the
immediate future to sense the significance of the approaching
tests for the history of the working class throughout Western
Europe. The present political conjuncture calls for a serious
and responsible clarification of the themes in Gramsci’s work
which are now commonly associated with the new design of Latin
communism.
At the same time, of course, Gramsci’s influence is
by no means confined to those countries where there exist major
Communist Parties, poised for entry into government. The
adoption of concepts from the Prison Notebooks has, in
fact, been especially marked in the theoretical and historical
work of the British left in recent years, and to a lesser extent
of the American left. The sudden phenomenon of very widespread
borrowing from Gramsci within Anglo-Saxon political culture
provides a second, more parochial prompting to re-examine his
legacy in these pages. For New Left Review was the first
socialist journal in Britain—possibly the first anywhere outside
Italy—to make deliberate and systematic use of Gramsci’s
theoretical canon to analyse its own national society, and to
debate a political strategy capable of transforming it. The
essays that sought to realise this project were published in
1964–5.1 At the time, Gramsci’s work was unfamiliar
in England: the articles in question were generally contested.2 By
1973–5, Gramscian themes and notions of a similar tenor were
ubiquitous. In particular, the central concept of ‘hegemony’,
first utilised as the leitmotif of the NLR theses of the early
sixties, has since enjoyed an exceptional fortune. Historians,
literary critics, philosophers, economists and political
scientists have employed it with ever-increasing frequency.3 Amidst
the profusion of usages and allusions, however, there has been
relatively little inspection of the actual texts in which
Gramsci developed his theory of hegemony. A more direct and
exact reflection on these is now overdue.
The purpose of this essay, then, will be to analyse
the forms and functions of Gramsci’s concept of hegemony in his Prison
Notebooks, and to assess their internal coherence as a
unified discourse; to consider their validity as an account of
the typical structures of class power in the bourgeois
democracies of the West; and finally to weigh their strategic
consequences for the struggle of the working class to achieve
emancipation and socialism. Its procedure will of necessity be
primarily philological: an attempt to fix with greater precision
what Gramsci said and meant in his captivity; to locate the
sources from which he derived the terms of his discourse; and to
reconstruct the network of oppositions and correspondences in
the thought of his contemporaries into which his writing was
inserted—in other words, the true theoretical context of his
work. These formal enquiries are the indispensable condition, it
will be argued, of any substantive judgement of Gramsci’s theory
of hegemony.
We may begin by recalling the most celebrated
passages of all in the Prison Notebooks—the legendary
fragments in which Gramsci contrasted the political structures
of ‘East’ and ‘West’, and the revolutionary strategies pertinent
to each of them. These texts represent the most cogent synthesis
of the essential terms of Gramsci’s theoretical universe, which
elsewhere are dispersed and scattered throughout the notebooks.
They do not immediately broach the problem of hegemony. However,
they assemble all the necessary elements for its emergence into
a controlling position in his discourse. The two central notes
focus on the relationship between state and civil society, in
Russia and in Western Europe respectively.4 In each
case, they do so by way of the same military analogy.
In the first, Gramsci discusses the rival strategies
of the high commands in the First World War, and concludes that
they suggest a critical lesson for class politics after the war:
General Krasnov has asserted (in his novel) that the
Entente did not wish for the victory of Imperial Russia for fear
that the Eastern Question would definitively be resolved in
favour of Tsarism, and therefore obliged the Russian General
Staff to adopt trench warfare (absurd, in view of the enormous
length of the front from the Baltic to the Black Sea, with vast
marshy and forest zones), whereas the only possible strategy was
a war of manoeuvre. This assertion is merely silly. In actual
fact, the Russian Army did attempt a war of manoeuvre and sudden
incursion, especially in the Austrian sector (but also in East
Prussia), and won successes as brilliant as they were ephemeral.
The truth is that one cannot choose the form of war one wants,
unless from the start one has a crushing superiority over the
enemy. It is well known what losses were incurred by the
stubborn refusal of the General Staffs to acknowledge that a war
of position was ‘imposed’ by the overall relation of forces in
conflict. A war of position is not, in reality, constituted
simply by actual trenches, but by the whole organisational and
industrial system of the territory which lies to the back of the
army in the field. It is imposed notably by the rapid fire-power
of cannons, machine-guns and rifles, by the armed strength that
can be concentrated at a particular spot, as well as by the
abundance of supplies that make possible the swift replacement
of material lost after an enemy breakthrough or retreat. A
further factor is the great mass of men under arms; they are of
a very unequal calibre, and are precisely only able to operate
as a mass force. It can be seen how on the Eastern Front it was
one thing to make an incursion into the Austrian sector, and
another into the German sector; and how even in the Austrian
sector, reinforced by picked German troops and commanded by
Germans, incursion tactics ended in disaster. The same thing
happened in the Polish Campaign of 1920; the seemingly
irresistible advance was halted before Warsaw by General
Weygand, on the line commanded by French officers. The very
military experts who are believers in wars of position, just as
they previously were in wars of manoeuvre, naturally do not
maintain that the latter should be expunged from military
science. They merely maintain that in wars among the more
industrially and socially advanced States, war of manoeuvre must
be considered reduced to more of a tactical than a strategic
function, occupying the same position as siege warfare
previously held in relation to it. The same reduction should be
effected in the art and science of politics, at least in the
case of the advanced States, where ‘civil society’ has become a
very complex structure and one that is resistant to the
catastrophic ‘incursions’ of the immediate economic element
(crises, depressions, and so on). The superstructures of civil
society are like the trench-systems of modern warfare. In war it
would happen sometimes that a fierce artillery attack seemed to
have destroyed the enemy’s entire defensive system, whereas in
fact it had only destroyed the outer surface of it; and at the
moment of their advance and attack the assailants would find
themselves confronted by a line of defence which was still
effective. The same thing happens in politics, during the great
economic crises. A crisis cannot give the attacking forces the
ability to organise with lightning speed in time and space;
still less can it endow them with fighting spirit. Similarly,
the defenders are not demoralised, nor do they abandon their
positions, even among the ruins, nor do they lose faith in their
own strength or in their own future. Of course, things do not
remain exactly as they were; but it is certain that one will not
find the element of speed, of accelerated time, of the
definitive forward march expected by the strategists of
political Cadornism. The last occurrence of the kind in the
history of politics was the events of 1917. They marked a
decisive turning-point in the history of the art and science of
politics.5
In the second text, Gramsci proceeds to a direct
counterposition of the course of the Russian Revolution and the
character of a correct strategy for socialism in the West, by
way of a contrast between the relationship of state and civil
society in the two geopolitical theatres:
It should be seen whether Trotsky’s famous theory
about the permanent character of the movement is not the
political reflection of … the general economic-cultural-social
conditions in a country in which the structures of national life
are embryonic and loose, and incapable of becoming ‘trench’ or
‘fortress’. In this case one might say that Trotsky, apparently
‘Western’, was in fact a cosmopolitan—that is, superficially
Western or European. Lenin on the other hand was profoundly
national and profoundly European … It seems to me that Lenin
understood that a change was necessary from the war of manoeuvre
applied victoriously in the East in 1917, to a war of position
which was the only possible form in the West—where, as Krasnov
observed, armies could rapidly accumulate endless quantities of
munitions, and where the social structures were of themselves
still capable of becoming heavily armed fortifications. This is
what the formula of the ‘united front’ seems to me to mean, and
it corresponds to the conception of a single front for the
Entente under the sole command of Foch. Lenin, however, did not
have time to expand his formula—though it should be remembered
that he could only have expanded it theoretically, whereas the
fundamental task was a national one; that is to say, it demanded
a reconnaissance of the terrain and identification of the
elements of trench and fortress represented by the elements of
civil society, and so on. In the East, the State was everything,
civil society was primordial and gelatinous; in the West, there
was a proper relationship between State and civil society, and
when the State trembled a sturdy structure of civil society was
at once revealed. The State was only an outer ditch, behind
which there was a powerful system of fortresses and earthworks:
more or less numerous from one State to the next it goes without
saying—but this precisely necessitated an accurate
reconnaissance of each individual country.6
There are a number of memorable themes in these two
extremely compressed and dense passages, which are echoed in
other fragments of the Notebooks. For the moment, our
intention is not to reconstitute and explore either of them, or
relate them to Gramsci’s thought as a whole. It will merely be
enough to set out the main apparent elements of which they are
composed, in a series of oppositions:
East West Civil Society Primordial/Gelatinous
Developed/Sturdy State Preponderant Balanced Strategy Manoeuvre
Position Tempo Speed Protraction While the terms of
each opposition are not given any precise definition in the
texts, the relations between the two sets initially appear clear
and coherent enough. A closer look, however, immediately reveals
certain discrepancies. Firstly, the economy is described as
making ‘incursions’ into civil society in the West as an
elemental force; the implication is evidently that it is
situated outside it. Yet the normal usage of the term ‘civil
society’ ever since Hegel had preeminently included the sphere
of the economy, as that of material needs; it was in this sense
that it was always employed by Marx and Engels. Here, on the
contrary, it seems to exclude economic relations. At the same
time, the second note contrasts the East, where the state is
‘everything’, with the West where the state and civil society
are in a ‘proper’ relationship. It can be assumed, without
forcing the text, that Gramsci meant by this something like a
‘balanced’ relationship; in a letter written a year or so
before, he refers to ‘an equilibrium of political society and
civil society’, where by political society he intended the
state.7 Yet the text goes on to say that in the war
of position in the West, the state constitutes only the ‘outer
ditch’ of civil society, which can resist its demolition. Civil
society thereby becomes a central core or inner redoubt, of
which the state is merely an external and dispensable surface.
Is this compatible with the image of a ‘balanced relationship’
between the two? The contrast in the two relationships between
state and civil society in East and West becomes a simple
inversion here—no longer preponderance versus equilibrium,
but one preponderance against another preponderance.
An accurate reading of these fragments is rendered
even more complex when it is realised that while their formal
objects of criticism are Trotsky and Luxemburg, their real
target may have been the Third Period of the Comintern. We can
surmise this from the date of their composition—somewhere
between 1930 and 1932 in the Notebooks—and from the
transparent reference to the Great Depression of 1929, on which
many of the sectarian conceptions of ‘social-fascism’ during the
Third Period were founded. Gramsci fought these ideas resolutely
from prison, and in doing so was led to reappropriate the
Comintern’s political prescriptions of 1921, when Lenin was
still alive, of tactical unity with all other working class
parties in the struggle against capital, which he himself along
with nearly every other important leader of the Italian
Communist Party had rejected at the time. Hence the ‘dislocated’
reference to the United Front in a text which seems to speak of
a quite different debate.
A comparison of these fragments with another crucial
text from the Notebooksreveals even more difficulties.
Gramsci alludes to the theme of ‘Permanent Revolution’ a number
of times. The other main passage in which he refers to it is
this:
The political concept of the so-called ‘Permanent
Revolution’, which emerged before 1848 as a scientifically
evolved expression of the Jacobin experience from 1789 to
Thermidor, belongs to a historical period in which the great
mass political parties and the economic trade unions did not yet
exist, and society was still in a state of fluidity from many
points of view, so to speak. There was a greater backwardness of
the countryside, and virtually complete monopoly of political
and State power by a few cities or even by a single one (Paris
in the case of France); a relatively rudimentary State
apparatus, and a greater autonomy of civil society from State
activity; a specific system of military forces and national
armed services; greater autonomy of the national economies from
the economic relations of the world market, and so on. In the
period after 1870, with the colonial expansion of Europe, all
these elements change. The internal and international
organisational relations of the State become more complex and
massive, and the Forty-Eightist formula of the ‘Permanent
Revolution’ is expanded and superseded in political science by
the formula of the ‘civil hegemony’. The same thing happens in
the art of politics as in military art: war of movement
increasingly becomes war of position, and it can be said that a
State will win a war in so far as it prepares for it minutely
and technically in peacetime. The massive structure of the
modern democracies, both as State organisations and as complexes
of associations in civil society, are for the art of politics
what ‘trenches’ and permanent fortifications of the front are
for the war of position. They render merely ‘partial’ the
element of movement which used to be the ‘whole’ of war. This
question is posed for the modern States, but not for the
backward countries or for the colonies, where forms which
elsewhere have been superseded and have become anachronistic are
still in vigour.8
Here the terms of the first two fragments are
recombined into a new order, and their meaning appears to shift
accordingly. ‘Permanent Revolution’ now clearly refers to Marx’s
‘Address to the Communist League of 1850’, when he advocated an
escalation from the bourgeois revolution which had just swept
Europe to a proletarian revolution. The Commune marks the end of
this hope. Henceforward war of position replaces permanent
revolution. The distinction East/West reappears in the form of a
demarcation of ‘modern democracies’ from ‘backward and colonial
societies’ where a war of movement still prevails. This change
in context corresponds to a shift in the relations between
‘state’ and ‘civil society’. In 1848, the state is ‘rudimentary’
and civil society is ‘autonomous’ from it. After 1870, the
internal and international organisation of the state becomes
‘complex and massive’, while civil society also becomes
correspondingly developed. It is now that the concept of
hegemony appears. For the new strategy necessary is precisely
that of ‘civil hegemony’. The meaning of the latter is
unexplained here; it is, however, clearly related to that of
‘war of position’. What is striking in this third fragment,
then, is its emphasis on the massive expansion of the Western
state from the late nineteenth century onwards, with a
subordinate allusion to a parallel development of civil society.
There is no explicit reversal of the terms, yet the context and
weight of the passage virtually imply a new prepotence of the
state.
It is not difficult, in effect, to discern in
Gramsci’s text the echo of Marx’s famous denunciation of the
‘monstrous parasitic machine’ of the Bonapartist state in
France. His periodisation is somewhat different from that of
Marx, since he dates the change from the victory of Thiers and
not that of Louis Napoleon, but the theme is that of The
Eighteenth Brumaire and The Civil War in France. In
the former, it will be remembered, Marx wrote: ‘Only under the
second Bonaparte does the State seem to have attained a
completely autonomous position. The State machine has
established itself so firmly vis-a-vis civil society that
the only leader it needs is the head of the Society of 10
December … The State enmeshes, controls, regulates, supervises
and regiments civil society from the most all-embracing
expressions of its life down to its most insignificant motions,
from its most general modes of existence down to the private
life of individuals ’.9 Gramsci makes no such extreme
claim. Yet, setting aside the rhetoric of Marx’s account, the
logic of Gramsci’s text leans in the same direction, to the
extent that it clearly implies that civil society has lost the
‘autonomy’ of the state which it once possessed.
There is thus an oscillation between at least three
different ‘positions’ of the state in the West in these initial
texts alone. It is in a ‘balanced relationship’ with civil
society, it is only an ‘outer surface’ of civil society, it is
the ‘massive structure’ which cancels the autonomy of civil
society. These oscillations, moreover, concern only the
relationship between the terms. The terms themselves, however,
are subject to the same sudden shifts of boundary and position.
In all the above quotations, the opposition is between ‘state’
and ‘civil society’. Yet elsewhere Gramsci speaks of the state
itself as inclusive of civil society, defining it thus: ‘The
general notion of the State includes elements which need to be
referred back to the notion of civil society (in the sense that
one might say that the State = political society + civil
society, in other words hegemony armoured with coercion).’10 Here
the distinction between ‘political society’ and ‘civil society’
is maintained, while the term ‘state’ encompasses the two. In
other passages, however, Gramsci goes further and directly
rejects any opposition between political and civil society, as a
confusion of liberal ideology. ‘The ideas of the Free Trade
movement are based on a theoretical error, whose practical
origin is not hard to identify; they are based on a distinction
between political society and civil society, which is rendered
and presented as an organic one, whereas in fact it is merely
methodological. Thus it is asserted that economic activity
belongs to civil society, and that the State must not intervene
to regulate it. But since in actual reality civil society and
State are one and the same, it must be made clear that
laissez-faire too is a form of State “regulation”, introduced
and maintained by legislative and coercive means.’11Political
society is here an express synonym for the state, and any
substantive separation of the two is denied. It is evident that
another semantic shift has occurred. In other words, the state
itself oscillates between three definitions:
State contrasts with Civil Society State encompasses Civil
Society State is identical with Civil Society Thus both the
terms and the relations between them are subject to sudden
variations or mutations. It will be seen that these shifts are
not arbitrary or accidental. They have a determinate meaning
within the architecture of Gramsci’s work. For the moment,
however, an elucidation of them can be deferred.
For there remains one further concept of Gramsci’s
discourse which is centrally related to the problematic of these
texts. That is, of course, hegemony. The term, it will be
remembered, occurs in the third passage as a strategy of ‘war of
position’ to replace the ‘war of manoeuvre’ of an earlier epoch.
This war of manoeuvre is identified with the ‘Permanent
Revolution’ of Marx in 1848. In the second text, the
identification reappears, but the reference here is to Trotsky
in the 1920s. The ‘war of position’ is now attributed to Lenin
and equated with the idea of the United Front. There is thus a
loop:
Civil Hegemony = War of Position = United Front
The next question is therefore naturally what
Gramsci meant precisely by war of position or civil hegemony.
Hitherto, we have been concerned with terms whose ancestry is
familiar. The notions of ‘state’ and ‘civil society’, dating
from the Renaissance and the Enlightenment respectively, present
no particular problems. However diverse their usage, they have
long formed part of common political parlance on the left. The
term ‘hegemony’ has no such immediate currency. In fact,
Gramsci’s concept in the Prison Notebooks is frequently
believed to be an entirely novel coinage—in effect, his own
invention.12 The word might perhaps be found in stray
phrases of writers before him, it is often suggested, but the
concept as a theoretical unit is his creation.
Nothing reveals the lack of scholarship from which
Gramsci’s legacy has suffered more than this widespread
illusion. For in fact the notion of hegemony had a long prior
history, before Gramsci’s adoption of it, that is of great
significance for understanding its later function in his work.
The term gegemoniya (hegemony) was one of the most
central political slogans in the Russian Social-Democratic
movement, from the late 1890s to 1917. The idea which it
codified first started to emerge in the writings of Plekhanov in
1883–4, where he urged the need for the Russian working class to
wage a political struggle against Tsarism, not merely an
economic struggle against its employers. In his founding
programme of the Emancipation of Labour Group in 1884, he argued
that the bourgeoisie in Russia was still too weak to take the
initiative in the struggle against Absolutism: the organised
working class would have to take up the demands of a
bourgeois-democratic revolution.13 Plekhanov in these
texts used the vague term ‘domination’ (gospodstvo) for
political power as such, and continued to assume that the
proletariat would support the bourgeoisie in a revolution in
which the latter would necessarily emerge in the end as the
leading class.14 By 1889, his emphasis had shifted
somewhat: ‘political freedom’ would now be ‘won by the working
class or not at all’—yet at the same time without challenging
the ultimate domination of capital in Russia.15 In
the next decade, his colleague Axelrod went further. In two
important pamphlets of 1898, polemicizing against Economism, he
declared that the Russian working class could and must play an
‘independent, leading role in the struggle against absolutism’,
for the ‘political impotence of all other classes’ conferred a
‘central, pre-eminent importance’ on the proletariat.16 ‘The
vanguard of the working class should systematically behave as
the leading detachment of democracy in general.’17 Axelrod
still oscillated between ascription of an ‘independent’ and a
‘leading’ role to the proletariat, and ascribed exaggerated
importance to gentry opposition to Tsarism, within what he
reaffirmed would be a bourgeois revolution. However, his
ever-greater emphasis on the ‘all-national revolutionary
significance’18 of the Russian working class soon
catalysed a qualitative theoretical change. For it was
henceforward the primacy of the proletariat in the bourgeois
revolution in Russia that would be unambiguously announced.
In a letter to Struve in 1901, demarcating
social-democratic from liberal perspectives in Russia, Axelrod
now stated as an axiom: ‘By virtue of the historical position of
our proletariat, Russian Social-Democracy can acquire hegemony (gegemoniya)
in the struggle against absolutism.’19 The younger
generation of Marxist theorists adopted the concept immediately.
In the same year, Martov was to write in a polemical article:
‘The struggle between the “critics” and “orthodox” Marxists is
really the first chapter of a struggle for political hegemony
between the proletariat and bourgeois democracy.’20 Lenin,
meanwhile, could without further ado refer in a letter written
to Plekhanov to ‘the famous “hegemony” of Social-Democracy’ and
call for a political newspaper as the sole effective means of
preparing a ‘real hegemony’ of the working class in Russia.21 In
the event, the emphasis pioneered by Plekhanov and Axelrod on
the vocation of the working class to adopt an ‘all-national’
approach to politics and to fight for the liberation of every
oppressed class and group in society was to be developed, with a
wholly new scope and eloquence, by Lenin in What Is to Be
Done? in 1902—a text read and approved in advance by
Plekhanov, Axelrod and Potresov, which ended precisely with an
urgent plea for the formation of the revolutionary newspaper
that was to be Iskra.
The slogan of the hegemony of the proletariat in the
bourgeois revolution was thus a common political inheritance for
Bolsheviks and Mensheviks alike at the Second Congress of the
RSDLP in 1903. After the scission, Potresov wrote a lengthy
article in Iskra reproaching Lenin for his ‘primitive’
interpretation of the idea of hegemony, summarised in the
celebrated call in What Is to Be Done? for
social-democrats to ‘go among all classes of the population’ and
organise ‘special auxiliary detachments’ for the working class
from them.22 Potresov complained that the gamut of
social classes aimed at by Lenin was too wide, while at the same
time the type of relationship he projected between the latter
and the proletariat was too peremptory—involving an impossible
‘assimilation’ rather than an alliance with them. A correct
strategy to win hegemony for the working class would betoken an
external orientation, not towards such improbable elements as
dissident gentry or students, but to democratic liberals, and
not denial but respect for their organisational autonomy. Lenin,
for his part, was soon accusing the Mensheviks of abandoning the
concept by their tacit acceptance of the leadership of Russian
capital in the bourgeois revolution against Tsarism. His call
for a ‘democratic dictatorship of the proletariat and peasantry’
in the 1905 revolution was precisely designed to give a
governmental formula to the traditional strategy, to which he
remained faithful.
After the defeat of the revolution, Lenin vehemently
denounced the Mensheviks for their relinquishment of the axiom
of hegemony, in a series of major articles in which he again and
again reasserted its political indispensability for any
revolutionary Marxist in Russia. ‘Because the
bourgeois-democratic tasks have been left unfulfilled, a
revolutionary crisis is still inevitable’, he wrote. ‘The tasks
of the proletariat that arise from this situation are fully and
unmistakably definite. As the only consistently revolutionary
class of contemporary society, it must be the leader in the
struggle of the whole people for a fully democratic revolution,
in the struggle of all the working and exploited people against
the oppressors and exploiters. The proletariat is revolutionary
only in so far as it is conscious of and gives effect to this
idea of the hegemony of the proletariat.’23 Menshevik
writers, claiming that since 1905 Tsarism had effected a
transition from a feudal to a capitalist state, had recently
declared the hegemony of the proletariat to be obsolete, since
the bourgeois revolution was now over in Russia.24 Lenin’s
response was thunderous: ‘To preach to the workers that what
they need is “not hegemony, but a class party” means to betray
the cause of the proletariat to the liberals; it means preaching
that Social-Democratic labour policy should be replaced by a
liberal labour policy. Renunciation of the idea of hegemony is
the crudest form of reformism in the Russian Social-Democratic
movement.’25
It was in these polemics, too, that Lenin repeatedly
contrasted a ‘hegemonic’ with a ‘guild’ or ‘corporatist’ phase
within proletarian politics. ‘From the standpoint of Marxism the
class, so long as it renounces the idea of hegemony or fails to
appreciate it, is not a class, or not yet a class, but a guild,
or the sum total of various guilds … It is the consciousness of
the idea of hegemony and its implementation through their own
activities that converts the guilds (tsekhi) as a whole
into a class.’26
The term hegemony, then, was one of the most widely
used and familiar notions in the debates of the Russian labour
movement before the October Revolution. After the revolution, it
fell into relative disuse in the Bolshevik Party—for one very
good reason. Forged to theorise the role of the working class in
a bourgeois revolution, it was rendered inoperative by the
advent of a socialist revolution. The scenario of a ‘democratic
dictatorship of workers and peasants’ remaining within the
bounds of capitalism never materialised, as is well known.
Trotsky, who had never believed in the coherence or feasibility
of Lenin’s programme for 1905, and whose contrary prediction of
a socialist revolution had been rapidly vindicated in 1917,
later wrote in his History of the Russian Revolution:
‘The popular and officially accepted idea of hegemony of the
proletariat in the democratic revolution … did not at all
signify that the proletariat would use a peasant uprising in
order with its support to place upon on the order of the day its
own historic task—that is, the direct transition to a socialist
society. The hegemony of the proletariat in the democratic
revolution was sharply distinguished from the dictatorship of
the proletariat, and polemically contrasted against it. The
Bolshevik Party had been educated in these ideas ever since
1905.’27 Trotsky was not to know that a ‘polemical
contrast’ between the ‘hegemony’ and the ‘dictatorship’ of the
proletariat would re-emerge again in an altered context, in
another epoch.
At the time, in the aftermath of October, the term
hegemony ceased to have much internal actuality in the USSR. It
survived, however, in the external documents of the Communist
International. At the first two World Congresses of the Third
International, the Comintern adopted a series of theses which
for the first time internationalised Russian usages of the
slogan of hegemony. The proletariat’s duty was to exercise
hegemony over the other exploited groups that were its class
allies in the struggle against capitalism, within its own soviet
institutions; there ‘its hegemony will permit the progressive
elevation of the semi-proletariat and poor peasantry’.28 If
it failed to lead the toiling masses in all arenas of social
activity, confining itself to its own particularist economic
objectives, it would lapse into corporatism. ‘The proletariat
becomes a revolutionary class only in so far as it does not
restrict itself to the framework of a narrow corporatism and
acts in every manifestation and domain of social life as the
guide of the whole working and exploited population … The
industrial proletariat cannot absolve its world-historical
mission, which is the emancipation of mankind from the yoke of
capitalism and of war, if it limits itself to its own particular
corporative interests and to efforts to improve its
situation—sometimes a very satisfactory one—within bourgeois
society.’29 At the Fourth Congress in 1922, the term
hegemony was—for what seems to be the first time—extended to the
domination of the bourgeoisie over the proletariat, if the
former succeeded in confining the latter to a corporate role by
inducing it to accept a division between political and economic
struggles in its class practice. ‘The bourgeoisie always seeks
to separate politics from economics, because it understands very
well that if it succeeds in keeping the working class within a
corporative framework, no serious danger can threaten its
hegemony.’30
The transmission of the notion of hegemony to
Gramsci, from the Russian to the Italian theatres of the
socialist movement, can with reasonable certainty be located in
these successive documents of the Comintern. The debates of the
pre-war RSDLP had become archival after the October Revolution;
although Gramsci spent a year in Moscow in 1922–3 and learnt
Russian, it is extremely unlikely that he would have had any
direct acquaintance with the texts of Axelrod, Martov, Potresov
or Lenin which debated the slogan of hegemony. On the other
hand, he naturally had an intimate knowledge of the Comintern
resolutions of the time: he was, indeed, a participant at the
Fourth World Congress itself. The consequences can be seen in
the Prison Notebooks: for Gramsci’s own treatment of the
idea of hegemony descends directly from the definitions of the
Third International.
We can now revert to Gramsci’s texts themselves.
Throughout the Prison Notebooks, the term ‘hegemony’
recurs in a multitude of different contexts. Yet there is no
doubt that Gramsci started from certain constant connotations of
the concept, which he derived from the Comintern tradition. For
in the first instance, the term refers in his writings to the
class alliance of the proletariat with other exploited groups,
above all the peasantry, in a common struggle against the
oppression of capital. Reflecting the experience of NEP, he laid
a somewhat greater emphasis on the need for ‘concessions’ and
‘sacrifices’ by the proletariat to its allies for it to win
hegemony over them, thereby extending the notion of
‘corporatism’ from a mere confinement to guild horizons or
economic struggles to any kind of ouvrierist isolation from the
other exploited masses. ‘The fact of hegemony presupposes that
account is taken of the interests and tendencies of the groups
over which hegemony is to be exercised, and that a certain
balance of compromise should be formed—in other words that the
leading group should make sacrifices of an economico-corporative
kind. But there is no doubt that although hegemony is
ethico-political, it must also be economic, must necessarily be
based on the decisive function exercised by the leading group in
the decisive nucleus of economic activity.’31 At the
same time, Gramsci also stressed more eloquently than any
Russian Marxist before 1917 the cultural ascendancy which the
hegemony of the proletariat over allied classes must involve.
‘Previously germinated ideologies become “party”, come into
conflict and confrontation, until only one of them, or at least
a single combination, tends to prevail, gaining the upper hand
and propagating itself throughout society. It thereby achieves
not only a unison of economic and political aims, but also
intellectual and moral unity, posing all questions over which
the struggle rages not on a corporate but on a universal plane.
It thus creates the hegemony of a fundamental social group over
a series of subordinate groups.’32
In a further development in the same theoretical
direction, Gramsci went on to counterpose the proletariat’s
necessary use of violence against the common enemy of the
exploited classes, and the resort to compromise within these
classes. In doing so, he was in effect restating the traditional
opposition between ‘dictatorship of the proletariat’ (over the
bourgeoisie) and ‘hegemony of the proletariat’ (over the
peasantry), so sharply recalled by Trotsky. ‘If the union of two
forces is necessary in order to defeat a third, a recourse to
arms and coercion (even supposing that these are available) can
be nothing more than a methodological hypothesis. The only
concrete possibility is compromise. Force can be employed
against enemies, but not against a part of one’s own side which
one wants to assimilate rapidly, and whose “goodwill” and
enthusiasm one needs.’33 The ‘union’ of which Gramsci
speaks here acquires a much more pronounced inflection in his
texts than in the Bolshevik vocabulary: the mechanical Russian
image of the smychka—or ‘yoking’—of working class and
peasantry, popularised during NEP, becomes the organic fusion of
a ‘new historical bloc’ in the Notebooks. Thus in the
same passage, Gramsci refers to the necessity to ‘absorb’ allied
social forces, in order ‘to create a new, homogeneous,
politico-economic historical bloc, without internal
contradictions’.34 The heightened register of the
formula corresponds to the novel charge given to cultural and
moral radiation in Gramsci’s usage of hegemony.
So far, the recurrent appeal in the Prison
Notebooks to the term hegemony represents no major departure
from the Russian revolutionary canon from which it was taken.
However, the very form of the prison writings was insensibly to
shift the significance and function of the concept, in their
context as a whole. For the characteristic medium in which
Gramsci presented his ideas was that of a protocol of general
axioms of political sociology, with ‘floating’
referents—sometimes allusively specified by class or regime or
epoch, but equally often ambiguously evocative of several
possible exemplars. This procedure, foreign to any other
Marxist, was of course dictated to Gramsci by the need to lull
the vigilance of the censor. Its result, however, was a constant
indeterminacy of focus, in which the bourgeoisie and the
proletariat can often alternate simultaneously as the
hypothetical subjects of the same passage—whenever, in fact,
Gramsci writes in the abstract of a ‘dominant class’. The mask
of generalisation into which Gramsci was thus frequently driven
had serious consequences for his thought: for it induced the
unexamined premise that the structural positions of the
bourgeoisie and the proletariat, in their respective revolutions
and their successive states, were historically equivalent. The
risks of such a tacit comparison will be seen in due course. At
present, what is important is to note the way in which the
‘desituated’ mode of discourse peculiar to so many of the texts
of Gramsci’s imprisonment permitted an imperceptible transition
to a much wider theory of hegemony than had ever been imagined
in Russia, which produced a wholly new theoretical field of
Marxist enquiry in Gramsci’s work.
For in effect, Gramsci extended the notion of
hegemony from its original application to the perspectives of
the working class in a bourgeois revolution against a feudal
order, to the mechanisms of bourgeois rule over the working
class in a stabilised capitalist society. There was a precedent
for this in the Comintern theses, it will be recollected. Yet
the passage in question was brief and isolated: it did not issue
into any more developed account of the sway of capital. Gramsci,
by contrast, now employed the concept of hegemony for a
differential analysis of the structures of bourgeois power in
the West. This was a new and decisive step. The passage from one
usage to the other was mediated through a set of generic maxims
in principle applicable to either. The result was an apparently
formal sequence of propositions about the nature of power in
history.
Symbolically, Gramsci took Machiavelli’s work as his
startingpoint for this new range of theory. Arguing the
necessity of a ‘dual perspective’ in all political action, he
wrote that at their ‘fundamental levels’, the two perspectives
corresponded to the ‘dual nature of Machiavelli’s
Centaur—half-animal and half-human’. For Gramsci, these were
‘the levels of force and consent, domination and hegemony,
violence and civilisation’.35 The terrain of
discourse here is manifestly universal, in emulation of the
manner of Machiavelli himself. An explicit set of oppositions is
presented, valid for any historical epoch:
Force Consent Domination Hegemony Violence Civilisation
The term ‘domination’ which is the antithesis of
‘hegemony’ recurs in another couplet to be found in other texts,
in opposition to ‘direction’. In the most important of these,
Gramsci wrote: ‘The supremacy of a social group assumes two
forms: “domination” and “intellectual and moral direction”. A
social group is dominant over enemy groups which it tends to
“liquidate” or subject with armed force, and is directive over
affinal and allied groups.’36 Here, the classical
Russian distinction between ‘dictatorship’ and ‘hegemony’ is
particularly clearly restated, in a slightly new terminology.
The critical significance of the passage, however, is that it
refers unambiguously not to the proletariat, but to the
bourgeoisie—for its subject is the role of the Moderates in the
Italian Risorgimento, and their ascendancy over the Action
Party. In other words, Gramsci has swung the compass of the
concept of hegemony towards a study of capitalist rule, albeit
still within the context of a bourgeois revolution (the original
framework for the notion in Russia). The elision of ‘direction’
with ‘hegemony’ is made later in the same paragraph on the
Risorgimento.37 The two are equated straightforwardly
in a contemporary letter written by Gramsci, when he remarks
that ‘Croce emphasises solely that moment in historico-political
activity which in politics is called “hegemony”, the moment of
consent, of cultural direction, to distinguish it from the
moment of force, of constraint, of statelegislative or police
intervention.’38
At the same time, the powerful cultural emphasis
that the idea of hegemony acquired in Gramsci’s work combined
with his theoretical application of it to traditional ruling
classes, to produce a new Marxist theory of intellectuals. For
one of the classical functions of the latter, Gramsci argued,
was to mediate the hegemony of the exploiting classes over the
exploited classes via the ideological systems of which they were
the organizing agents. Croce himself represented for Gramsci one
of those ‘great intellectuals who exercise a hegemony that
presupposes a certain collaboration, or voluntary and active
consent’ from the subordinate classes. 39
The next question that Gramsci posed was specific to
his thought. Where are the two functions of ‘domination’ and
‘direction/hegemony’ exercised? In particular, what is the site
of ‘hegemony’? Gramsci’s first and firmest answer is that
hegemony (direction) pertains to civil society, and coercion
(domination) to the state. ‘We can now fix two major
superstructural levels—one that may be called “civil society”,
that is the ensemble of organisms commonly called “private”, and
the other that of “political society” or the state. These two
levels correspond on the one hand to the function of “hegemony”
which the dominant group exercises throughout society and on the
other hand to that of “direct domination” or command exercised
through the State and “juridical” government.’40 There
was no precedent for such a theorisation in the Russian debates.
The reason is evident. Gramsci was by now unmistakably more
concerned with the constellation of bourgeois political power in
an orthodox capitalist social order. The allusion to the
‘private’ institutions of civil society—inappropriate to any
social formation in which the working class exercises collective
power—indicates the real object of his thought here. In a
contemporary letter, Gramsci referred even more directly to the
contrast within the context of capitalism, writing of the
opposition between political society and civil society as the
respective sites of two modes of class power: ‘political society
(or dictatorship, or coercive apparatus to ensure that the
popular masses conform to the type of production and economy of
a given moment)’ was counterposed to ‘civil society (or hegemony
of a social group over the whole national society exercised
through so-called private organisations, like the church, trade
unions, schools and so on)’.41 Here the listing of
church and schools as instruments of hegemony within the private
associations of civil society puts the application of the
concept to the capitalist societies of the West beyond any
doubt. The result is to yield these unambiguous oppositions:
Hegemony Domination = = Consent Coercion = = Civil Society
State It has, however, already been seen that Gramsci did
not use the antonyms of state and civil society univocally. Both
the terms and the relationship between them undergo different
mutations in his writings. Exactly the same is true of the term
‘hegemony’. For the texts quoted above contrast with others in
which Gramsci speaks of hegemony not as a pole of ‘consent’ in
contrast to another of ‘coercion’, but as itself a synthesis of
consent and coercion. Thus, in a note on French political
history, he commented: ‘The normal exercise of hegemony on the
now classical terrain of a parliamentary regime is characterised
by a combination of force and consent which form variable
equilibria, without force ever prevailing too much over
consent.’42 Here Gramsci’s reorientation of the
concept of hegemony towards the advanced capitalist countries of
Western Europe and the structures of bourgeois power within them
acquires a further thematic accentuation. The notion is now
directly connected with the phenomenon of parliamentary
democracy, peculiar to the West. At the same time, parallel with
the shift in the function of hegemony from consent to
consent-coercion, there occurs a relocation of its topographical
position. For in another passage, Gramsci writes of the
executive, legislature and judiciary of the liberal state as
‘organs of political hegemony’.43 Here hegemony is
firmly situated within the state—no longer confined to civil
society. The nuance of ‘political hegemony’, contrasting with
‘civil hegemony’, underlines the residual opposition between
political society and civil society, which as we know is one of
Gramsci’s variants of the couplet state and civil society. In
other words, hegemony is here located not in one of the two
terms, but in both.
State Civil Society = = Political Hegemony Civil Hegemony
This version cannot be reconciled with the preceding
account, which remains the predominant one in the Notebooks.
For in the first, Gramsci counterposes hegemony to political
society or the state, while in the second the state itself
becomes an apparatus of hegemony. In yet another version, the
distinction between civil and political society disappears
altogether: consent and coercion alike become co-extensive with
the state. Gramsci writes: ‘The State (in its integral meaning)
is dictatorship + hegemony.’44 The oscillations in
the connotation and location of hegemony amplify those of the
original pair of terms themselves. Thus in the enigmatic mosaic
that Gramsci assembled in prison, the words ‘state’, ‘civil
society’, ‘political society’, ‘hegemony’, ‘domination’ or
‘direction’ all undergo a persistent slippage. We will now try
to show that this slippage is neither accidental nor arbitrary.
2
VARIANTS
Three distinct versions of the relations between
Gramsci’s key concepts are simultaneously discernible in his Prison
Notebooks, once the problematic of hegemony shifted away
from the social alliances of the proletariat in the East towards
the structures of bourgeois power in the West. It will be seen
that each of these corresponds to a fundamental problem for
Marxist analysis of the bourgeois state, without providing an
adequate answer to it: the variation between the versions is
precisely the decipherable symptom of Gramsci’s awareness of the
aporia of his solutions. To indicate the limits of Gramsci’s
axioms, of course, more than a philological demonstration of
their lack of internal coherence is needed. However summary,
certain political assessments of their external correspondence
with the nature of the contemporary bourgeois states in the West
will be suggested.
At the same time, however, these will remain within
the limits of Gramsci’s own system of categories. The question
of whether the latter in fact provide the best point of
departure for a scientific analysis of the structures of
capitalist power today will not be prejudged. In particular, the
binary oppositions of ‘state and civil society’ and ‘coercion
and consent’ will be respected as the central elements of
Gramsci’s discourse; it is their application, rather than their
function, in his Marxism that will be reviewed. The difficulties
of any too-dualist theory of bourgeois class power will not be
explored here. It is evident, in effect, that the whole range of
directly economic constraints to which the exploited classes
within capitalism are subjected cannot immediately be classified
within either of the political categories of coercion or
consent—armed force or cultural persuasion. Similarly, a formal
dichotomy of state and civil society, however necessary as a
preliminary instrument, cannot in itself yield specific
knowledge of the complex relations between the different
institutions of a capitalist social formation (some of which
typically occupy intermediate positions on the borders of the
two). It is possible that the analytic issues with which Gramsci
was most concerned in fact need to be reconceptualised within a
new order of categories, beyond his binary landmarks. These
problems, however, fall outside the scope of a textual
commentary. For our purposes here, it will be sufficient to stay
on the terrain of Gramsci’s own enquiry—still today that of a
pioneer.
We may start by examining the first and most
striking configuration of Gramsci’s terms cited above, the most
important for the ulterior destiny of his work. Its central text
is the initial passage cited in this essay, in which Gramsci
writes of the difference between East and West, and says that in
the East, the ‘State is everything’, while in the West, the
state is an ‘outer ditch’ of the inner fortress of civil
society, which can survive the worst tremors in the state,
because it is not ‘primordial and gelatinous’ as in the East,
but robust and structured. A ‘war of manoeuvre’ is thus
appropriate in the East, a ‘war of position’ in the West. This
thesis can then be linked to the companion argument, reiterated
in so many other texts, that the state is the site of the armed
domination or coercion of the bourgeoisie over the exploited
classes, while civil society is the arena of its cultural
direction or consensual hegemony over them—the opposition
between ‘force and consent, coercion and persuasion, state and
church, political society and civil society’.1 The
result is to aggregate a combined set of oppositions for the
distinction East/West:
East West State Civil Society / / Civil Society State Coercion
Consent Domination Hegemony Manoeuvre Position In
other words, the preponderance of civil society over the state
in the West can be equated with the predominance of ‘hegemony’
over ‘coercion’ as the fundamental mode of bourgeois power in
advanced capitalism. Since hegemony pertains to civil society,
and civil society prevails over the state, it is the cultural
ascendancy of the ruling class that essentially ensures the
stability of the capitalist order. For in Gramsci’s usage here,
hegemony means the ideological subordination of the working
class by the bourgeoisie, which enables it to rule by consent.
Now the preliminary aim of this formula is evident.
It is to establish one obvious and fundamental difference
between Tsarist Russia and Western Europe—the existence of
representative political democracy. As such, it is analogous to
Lenin’s lapidary formula that the Russian Tsars ruled by force
and the Anglo-French bourgeoisie by deception and concessions.2 The
great theoretical merit of Gramsci was to have posed the problem
of this difference far more persistently and coherently than any
other revolutionary before or since. Nowhere in the writings of
Lenin or Trotsky, or other Bolshevik theorists, can there be
found any sustained or systematic reflection on the enormous
historical divide within Europe traced by the presence—even if
still fitful and incomplete in their time—of parliamentary
democracy in the West, and its absence in the East. A problem
registered at most in marginal asides in the Bolshevik tradition
was developed for the first time into a commanding theme for
Marxist theory by Gramsci.
At the same time, the first solution he sketches in
the Prison Notebooks is radically unviable: the simple
location of ‘hegemony’ within civil society, and the attribution
of primacy to civil society over the state. This equation, in
effect, corresponds very exactly to what might be called a
common-sense view of bourgeois democracy in the West on the
left—a view widely diffused in militant social-democratic
circles since the Second World War.3 For this
conception, the State in the West is not a violent machine of
police repression as it was in Tsarist Russia: the masses have
access to it through regular democratic elections, which
formally permit the possibility of a socialist government. Yet
experience shows that these elections never produce a government
dedicated to the expropriation of capital and the realisation of
socialism. Fifty years after the advent of universal suffrage,
such a phenomenon seems further away than ever. What is the
reason for this paradox? It must lie in the prior ideological
conditioning of the proletariat before the electoral moment as
such. The central locus of power must therefore be sought within
civil society—above all, in capitalist control of the means of
communication (press, radio, television, cinema, publishing),
based on control of the means of production (private property).
In a more sophisticated variant, the real inculcation of
voluntary acceptance of capitalism occurs not so much through
the ideological indoctrination of the means of communication, as
in the invisible diffusion of commodity fetishism through the
market or the instinctual habits of submission induced by the
work-routines of factories and offices—in other words, directly
within the ambit of the means of production themselves. Yet
whether the primary emphasis is given to the effect of cultural
or economic apparatuses, the analytic conclusion is the same. It
is the strategic nexus of civil society which is believed to
maintain capitalist hegemony within a political democracy, whose
state institutions do not directly debar or repress the masses.4 The
system is maintained by consent, not coercion. Therefore the
main task of socialist militants is not combat with an armed
state, but ideological conversion of the working class to free
it from submission to capitalist mystifications.
This characteristic syndrome of left social
democracy contains a number of illusions. The first and most
immediate of its errors is precisely the notion that the
ideological power of the bourgeoisie in Western social
formations is exercised above all in the sphere of civil
society, its hegemony over which subsequently neutralises the
democratic potential of the representative state. The working
class has access to the state (elections to parliament), but
does not exercise it to achieve socialism because of its
indoctrination by the means of communication. In fact, it might
be said that the truth is if anything the inverse: the general
form of the representative state—bourgeois democracy —is itself
the principal ideological linchpin of Western capitalism, whose
very existence deprives the working class of the idea of
socialism as a different type of state, and the means of
communication and other mechanisms of cultural control
thereafter clinch this central ideological ‘effect’. Capitalist
relations of production allocate all men and women into
different social classes, defined by their differential access
to the means of production. These class divisions are the
underlying reality of the wage-contract between juridically free
and equal persons that is the hallmark of this mode of
production. The political and economic orders are thereby
formally separated under capitalism. The bourgeois state thus by
definition ‘represents’ the totality of the population,
abstracted from its distribution into social classes, as
individual and equal citizens. In other words, it presents to
men and women their unequal positions in civil society as if
they were equal in the state. Parliament, elected every four or
five years as the sovereign expression of popular will, reflects
the fictive unity of the nation back to the masses as if it were
their own self-government. The economic divisions within the
‘citizenry’ are masked by the juridical parity between
exploiters and exploited, and with them the complete separation
and non-participation of the masses in the work of parliament.
This separation is then constantly presented and represented to
the masses as the ultimate incarnation of liberty: ‘democracy’
as the terminal point of history. The existence of the
parliamentary state thus constitutes the formal framework of all
other ideological mechanisms of the ruling class. It provides
the general code in which every specific message elsewhere is
transmitted. The code is all the more powerful because the
juridical rights of citizenship are not a mere mirage: on the
contrary, the civic freedoms and suffrages of bourgeois
democracy are a tangible reality, whose completion was
historically in part the work of the labour movement itself, and
whose loss would be a momentous defeat for the working class.5
By comparison, the economic improvements won by
reforms within the framework of the representative
state—apparently more material—have typically left less
ideological mark on the masses in the West. In the leading
imperialist countries, the steady rise in the standard of living
of the working class for twenty-five years after the Second
World War has been a critical element in the political stability
of metropolitan capitalism. Yet the material component of
popular assent to it, the subject of traditional polemics over
the effects of reformism, is inherently unstable and volatile,
since it tends to create a constant progression of expectations
whose satisfaction no national capitalist economy can totally
ensure, even during long waves of international boom, let alone
phases of recession; its very ‘dynamism’ is thus potentially
destabilizing and capable of provoking crises when growth
fluctuates or stalls. By contrast, the juridico-political
component of consent induced by the parliamentary state is much
more stable: the capitalist polity is not subject to the same
conjunctural vicissitudes. The historical occasions on which it
has been actively questioned by working class struggles have
been infinitely fewer in the West. In other words, the ideology
of bourgeois democracy is far more potent than that of any
welfare reformism, and forms the permanent syntax of the
consensus instilled by the capitalist state.
It can now be seen why Gramsci’s primary formula was
mistaken. It is impossible to partition the ideological
functions of bourgeois class power between civil society and the
state, in the way that he initially sought to do. The
fundamental form of the Western parliamentary state—the
juridical sum of its citizenry—is itself the hub of the
ideological apparatuses of capitalism. The ramified complexes of
the cultural control systems within civil society—radio,
television, cinema, churches, newspapers, political
parties—undoubtedly play a critical complementary role in
assuring the stability of the class order of capital. So too, of
course, do the distorting prism of market relations and the
numbing structure of the labour process within the economy. The
importance of these systems should certainly not be
underestimated. But neither should it be exaggerated or—above
all—counterposed to the cultural-ideological role of the state
itself.
A certain vulgar leftism has traditionally isolated
the problem of consent from its structural context, and
hypostasised it as the unique and distinguishing feature of
capitalist rule in the West, which becomes reduced to the
sobriquet of ‘parliamentarism’. To refute this error, many
Marxists have pointed out that all ruling classes in history
have normally obtained the consent of the exploited classes to
their own exploitation—feudal lords or slave-owning latifundists
no less than industrial entrepreneurs. The objection is, of
course, correct. But it is not an adequate reply, unless it is
accompanied by an accurate definition of the differentia
specifica of the consent won from the working class to the
accumulation of capital in the West today—in other words the
form and content of the bourgeois ideology which it is induced
to accept. Nicos Poulantzas, whose work Political Power and
Social Classes contains many critically acute comments on
the Prison Notebooks, in effect dismisses Gramsci’s
concern with the problem, remarking that the only novelty of
this consent is its claim to rationality—i.e. its non-religious
character. ‘The specific characteristic of (capitalist)
ideologies is not at all, as Gramsci believed, that they procure
a more or less active “consent” from the dominated classes
towards political domination, since this is a general
characteristic of any dominant ideology. What specifically
defines the ideologies in question is that they do not aim to be
accepted by the dominated classes according to the principle of
participation in the sacred: they explicitly declare themselves
and are accepted as scientific techniques.’6 In a
similar fashion, Ernest Mandel has written in his Late
Capitalism that the major contemporary form of capitalist
ideology in the West is an appeal to technological rationality
and a cult of experts: ‘Belief in the omnipotence of technology
is the specific form of bourgeois ideology in late capitalism.’7 These
claims involve a serious misconception.
For the peculiarity of the historical consent won
from the masses within modern capitalist social formations is by
no means to be found in its mere secular reference or technical
awe. The novelty of this consent is that it takes the
fundamental form of a belief by the masses that they exercise an
ultimate self-determination within the existing social order. It
is thus not acceptance of the superiority of an acknowledged
ruling class (feudal ideology), but credence in the democratic
equality of all citizens in the government of the nation—in
other words, disbelief in the existence of any ruling class. The
consent of the exploited in a capitalist social formation is
thus of a qualitatively new type, which has suggestively
produced its own etymological extension: consensus, or mutual
agreement. Naturally, the active pressure of bourgeois ideology
coexists and combines in a wide number of mixed forms with much
older and less articulated ideological habits and traditions—in
particular, those of passive resignation to the way of the world
and diffidence in any possibility of changing it, generated by
the differential knowledge and confidence characteristic of any
class society.8 The legacy of these diuturnal
traditions does indeed often take the modern guise of deference
to technical necessity. They do not, however, represent any real
departure from previous patterns of class domination; the
condition of their continued efficacy today is their insertion
into an ideology of representative democracy which overarches
them. For it is the freedom of bourgeois democracy alone that
appears to establish the limits of what is socially possible for
the collective will of a people, and thereby can render the
bounds of its impotence tolerable.9
Gramsci himself was, in fact, very conscious of the
need for careful discrimination of the successive historical
forms of ‘consent’ by the exploited to their exploitation, and
for analytic differentiation of its components at any one moment
of time. He reproached Croce precisely for assuming in his History
of Liberty that all ideologies prior to liberalism were of
the ‘same sere and indistinct colour, devoid of development or
conflict’—stressing the specificity of the hold of religion on
the masses of Bourbon Naples, the power of the appeal to the
nation which succeeded it in Italy, and at the same time the
possibility of popular combinations of the two.10Elsewhere,
he contrasted the epochs of the French Revolution and
Restoration in Europe precisely in terms of the distinct types
of consent—‘direct’ and ‘indirect’—that they obtained from the
oppressed, and the forms of suffrage—universal and
censitary—that corresponded to them.11 Paradoxically,
however, Gramsci never produced any comprehensive account of the
history or structure of bourgeois democracy in his Prison
Notebooks. The problem that confers its deepest meaning on
his central theoretical work remains the horizon rather than the
object of his texts. Part of the reason why the initial
equations of his discourse on hegemony were miscalculated, was
due to this absence. Gramsci was not wrong in his constant
reversion to the problem of consent in the West: until the full
nature and role of bourgeois democracy is grasped, nothing can
be understood of capitalist power in the advanced industrial
countries today. At the same time, it should be clear why
Gramsci was mistaken in his first location of ‘consent’ within
civil society. For, in fact, the very nature of this consent
excludes such an allocation, since it is precisely the
parliamentary representative state that first and foremost
induces it.
Let us now look at Gramsci’s second version of the
relationship between his terms. In this, he no longer ascribes
to civil society a preponderance over the state, or a unilateral
localisation of hegemony to civil society. On the contrary,
civil society is presented as in balance or equilibrium with the
state, and hegemony is distributed between state—or ‘political
society’—and civil society, while itself being redefined to
combine coercion and consent. These formulations express
Gramsci’s unease with his first version, and his acute
awareness—despite and against it—of the central ideological role
of the Western capitalist state. He does not merely register
this role in general. Yet his comments on the particular
dimensions of the state which specialise in the performance of
it are selective, focusing on its subordinate rather than its
superordinate institutions. For Gramsci’s specific references to
the ideological functions of the state are concerned not so much
with parliament, as with education and law—the school system and
the judicial system. ‘Every State is ethical in so far as one of
its most important functions is to elevate the great mass of the
population to a given cultural and moral level, a level or
standard which corresponds to the needs of development of the
forces of production and hence to the interests of the dominant
classes. The school as a positive educational function and the
courts as a negative and repressive educational function are the
most important such activities of the State. But in reality a
multiplicity of other so-called private initiatives and
activities tend towards the same end, which constitute the
apparatus of political and cultural hegemony of the ruling
class.’12
This emphasis is extremely important. It underlines
all the distance between Gramsci and many of his later
commentators, whatever the limits of Gramsci’s development of
it. Yet at the same time, it cannot be accepted as a true
correction of the first version. Gramsci now grasps the
co-presence of ideological controls within civil society and the
state. But this gain on one plane is offset by a loss of clarity
on another. Hegemony, which was earlier allocated to civil
society only, is now exercised by the state as well.
Simultaneously, however, its meaning tends to change: it now no
longer indicates cultural supremacy alone, for it also includes
coercion. ‘The normal exercise of hegemony’ is now
‘characterised by a combination of force and consent’. The
result is that Gramsci now commits an error from the other
direction. For coercion is precisely a legal monopoly of the
capitalist state. In Weber’s famous definition, the state is the
institution which enjoys a monopoly of legitimate violence over
a given territory.13 It alone possesses an army and a
police—‘groups of men specialised in the use of repression’
(Engels). Thus it is not true that hegemony as coercion +
consent is co-present in civil society and the state alike. The
exercise of repression is juridically absent from civil society.
The state reserves it as an exclusive domain.14 This
brings us to a first fundamental axiom governing the nature of
power in a developed capitalist social formation. There is
always a structural asymmetry in the distribution of the
consensual and coercive functions of this power. Ideology is
shared between civil society and the state: violence pertains to
the state alone. In other words, the state enters twice over
into any equation between the two.
It is possible that one reason why Gramsci had
difficulty in isolating this asymmetry was that Italy had
witnessed in 1920–2 the exceptional emergence of military squads
organised by the fascists, which operated freely outside the
state apparatus proper. The structural monopoly of violence by
the capitalist state was thus to some extent masked by
conjunctural commando operations (Gramsci’s term) within civil
society. Yet in fact, of course, the squadristi could
only assault and sack working class institutions with impunity
because they had the tacit coverage of the police and army.
Gramsci, with his customary lucidity, was naturally well aware
of this: ‘In the present struggles it often happens that a
weakened State machine is like a flagging army: commandos, or
private armed organisations, enter the field to accomplish two
tasks—to use illegality, while the State appears to remain
within legality, and thereby to reorganise the State itself.’15 Commenting
on the March on Rome, he wrote: ‘There could be no “civil war”
between the State and the fascist movement, only a sporadic
violent action to modify the leadership of the State and reform
its administrative apparatus. In the civil guerrilla struggle,
the fascist movement was not against the State, but aligned with
it.’16 The relatively atypical episode of the fascist
squads—whose expeditions could only be ‘sporadic’—does not in
fact seem to have had any notable effect on the balance of
Gramsci’s thought.
More important for the uncertainty of his account of
the relationship between state and civil society in this respect
was the recurrent tendency of his theory towards an
over-extension of its concepts. His dissolution of the police
into a wider and vaguer social phenomenon is a not untypical
example. ‘What is the police? It is certainly not merely the
official organisation, juridically acknowledged and assigned to
the function of public security, that is usually understood by
the term. The latter is the central nucleus that has formal
responsibility for the “police”, which is actually a much vaster
organisation, in which a large part of the population of a State
participates, directly or indirectly, with more or less precise
and definite links, permanently or occasionally.’17In
fact, it is striking that in precisely the area of law, which
particularly interested him as a function of the state, Gramsci
could simultaneously note the absence of any coercive equivalent
to its sanctions within civil society, yet argue that legality
should nevertheless be regarded as a more ubiquitous system of
pressures and compulsions at work in civil society as much as in
the state, to produce particular moral and cultural standards.
‘The concept of “law” should be extended to include those
activities which today are designated “juridically neutral” and
are within the domain of civil society, which operates without
taxative sanctions or obligations, but nonetheless exercises a
collective pressure and obtains objective results in determining
customs, ways of thinking and behaving, morals, and so on.’18 The
result is a structural indistinction between law and custom,
juridical rules and conventional norms, which impedes accurate
demarcation of the respective provinces of civil society or the
state in a capitalist social formation. Gramsci was never quite
able to fix the asymmetry between the two: his successive
formulations constantly grope towards it, without ever exactly
reaching it.
For Gramsci’s third version of relationship between
his terms represents a final attempt to grasp his elusive
object. In this version, the state now includes ‘political
society’ and ‘civil society’ alike. In effect, it radicalises
the categorial fusion incipient in the second version. There is
now no longer merely a distribution of hegemony, as a synthesis
of coercion and consent, across state and civil society. State
and civil society themselves are merged into a larger suzerain
unity. ‘By the State should be understood not merely the
governmental apparatus, but also the “private” apparatus of
hegemony or civil society.’19 The conclusion of this
argument is the abrupt dictum: ‘In reality civil society and
State are one and the same.’20 In other words, the
state becomes coextensive with the social formation, as in
international usage. The concept of civil society as a distinct
entity disappears. ‘Civil society is also part of the “State”,
indeed is the State itself.’21 These formulations can
be said to reveal Gramsci’s frequent awareness that the role of
the state in some sense ‘exceeds’ that of civil society in the
West. They thus constitute an important correction of his second
version. Yet once again, the gain on the new terrain is
accompanied by a loss on the previous one. For in this final
version, the very distinction between state and civil society is
itself cancelled. This solution has grave consequences, which
undermine any scientific attempt to define the specificity of
bourgeois democracy in the West.
The results can be seen in the adoption of this
version by Louis Althusser and his colleagues. For if the first
version of Gramsci’s equations was above all appropriated by
left currents within European social democracy after the war,
the third version has been more recently utilised by left
currents within European communism. The origins of this adoption
can be found in a well-known passage of For Marx, in
which Althusser, equating the notion of ‘civil society’ with
‘individual economic behaviour’ and attributing its descent to
Hegel, dismissed it as alien to historical materialism.22 In
fact, of course, while the young Marx did use the term primarily
to refer to the sphere of economic needs and activities, it is
far from the case that it disappears from his mature writings.
If its earlier signification disappears from Capital(with
the emergence of the concepts of forces/relations of
production), the term itself does not—for it had another meaning
for Marx, that was not synonymous with individual economic
needs, but was a generic designation for all non-state
institutions in a capitalist social formation. Marx not only
never abandoned this function of the concept of ‘civil society’,
his later political writings repeatedly revolve on a central
usage of it. Thus the whole of The Eighteenth Brumaire is
built on an analysis of Bonapartism which starts from the
assertion that: ‘The State enmeshes, controls, regulates,
supervises and regiments civil society from the most
all-embracing expressions of its life down to its most
insignificant motions, from its most general modes of existence
down to the private life of individuals.’23
It was this usage which Gramsci took over in his
prison writings. In doing so, however, he delimited the concept
of ‘civil society’ much more precisely. In Gramsci, civil
society does not refer to the sphere of economic relations, but
is precisely contrasted with it as a system of superstructural
institutions that is intermediary between economy and state.
‘Between the economic structure and the State, with
its legislation and coercion, stands civil society.’24 This
is why Gramsci’s list of the institutions of hegemony in civil
society rarely includes factories or plants—precisely the
economic apparatuses that many of his disciples today believe to
be primary in inculcating ideological subordination among the
masses. (If anything, in his Turin writings, if not in his notes
on Americanism in prison, Gramsci often tended to regard the
discipline of these as schools of socialism rather than
capitalism.) Gramsci’s definition of the term ‘civil society’
can thus be described as a refinement of its use in the late
Marx, explicitly dissociating it from its economic origins. At
the same time, we have just seen that in his last version of the
dyad state and civil society he abandons the distinction between
the two altogether, to proclaim their identity. Can the term,
however, be simply rejected even in its non-economic usage?
There is no question that its variegated passage through Locke,
Ferguson, Rousseau, Kant, Hegel and Marx has loaded it with
multiple ambiguities and confusions.25 It will
doubtless be necessary to frame a new and unequivocal concept in
the future, within a developed theory of the total articulation
of capitalist social formations. But until this is available,
the term ‘civil society’ remains a necessary practico-indicative
concept, to designate all those institutions and mechanisms
outside the boundaries of the state system proper. In other
words, its function is to draw an indispensable line of
demarcation within the politico-ideological superstructures of
capitalism.
Once he had rejected the notion of civil society,
Althusser was thus later logically led to a drastic assimilation
of Gramsci’s final formula, which effectively abolishes the
distinction between state and civil society. The result was the
thesis that ‘churches, parties, trade unions, families, schools,
newspapers, cultural ventures’ in fact all constitute
‘Ideological State Apparatuses’.26 Explaining this
notion, Althusser declared: ‘It is unimportant whether the
institutions in which they (ideologies) are realised are
“public” or “private” ’—for these all indifferently form sectors
of a single controlling state which is ‘the precondition for any
distinction between public and private’.27 The
political reasons for this sudden and arbitrary theoretical
decision are not entirely clear. However, it seems probable that
they were in large measure a product of the attraction exercised
by the Chinese Cultural Revolution in the late sixties on
semi-oppositional sectors of the European Communist Parties. The
revolutionary character officially claimed for the process in
China could, in effect, only be squared with classical Marxist
definitions of a revolution—the overthrow and destruction of a
state machine—by decreeing all manifestations of culture to be
state apparatuses.28 In the Chinese press of the time
such manifestations were, indeed, typically discerned in the
psychological traits displayed by individuals. To provide
Marxist credentials for this ‘revolution of the spirits’
underway in China, a radical redefinition of the state was
necessary. There is little need to dwell today on the inadequacy
of this procedure for any rational account of the Cultural
Revolution, now an archivised chapter in the history of the CCP.
Much more serious were its potential consequences for a
responsible socialist politics in the West.
For once the position is adopted that all
ideological and political superstructures—including the family,
reformist trade unions and parties, and private media—are by
definition state apparatuses, in strict logic it becomes
impossible and unnecessary to distinguish between bourgeois
democracies and fascism. For the fact that in the latter total
state control over trade unions or mass media was
institutionalised would, according to this reasoning, be—to use
Althusser’s phrase—‘unimportant’. A similar conflation of state
and civil society could conversely lead younger disciples of the
Frankfurt School at the same time to argue that ‘liberal
democracy’ in post-war Germany was functionally equivalent to
fascism in pre-war Germany, since the family now fulfilled the
authoritarian instance previously occupied by the police, as
part of the state system. The unscientific character of such
theses is obvious; the European working class paid heavily for
anticipations of them in the twenties and early thirties. The
boundaries of the state are not a matter of indifference to
Marxist theory or revolutionary practice. It is essential to be
able to chart them accurately. To blur them is, in fact, to
misunderstand the specific role and efficacy of the
superstructures outside the state within bourgeois democracy.
Ralph Miliband, in a prescient criticism of the whole notion of
‘Ideological State Apparatuses’, correctly emphasised this. ‘To
suggest that the relevant institutions are actually part of the
State system does not seem to me to accord with reality, and
tends to obscure the difference in this respect between these
political systems and systems where ideological institutions are
indeed part of a State monopolistic system of power. In the
former systems, ideological institutions do retain a very high
degree of autonomy; and are therefore the better able to conceal
the degree to which they do belong to the system of capitalist
power.’29
So far as Althusser was concerned, it would in fact
have been unjust to ascribe any identification of the structures
of fascism and bourgeois democracy to him: there is no sign that
he was ever tempted by such ultra-leftist errors—or,
alternatively, by the reformist consequences that could also be
formally deduced from the idea that trade-union locals or cinema
studios were part of the state apparatus in the West (in which
case the victory of a communist slate or the making of a
militant film would putatively count as gradual conquests of
‘parts’ of a divisible state apparatus—in defiance of the
fundamental Marxist tenet of the political unity of the
bourgeois state which precisely necessitates a revolution to end
it). The reason for the actual innocuousness of a theory that
was so potentially dangerous lay in its inspiration. Designed
for an arcane compliance with events in China, its exoteric
applications in the West lacked any local impetus. The real mark
of the thesis was not its political gravity for the working
class, so much as its levity.
The case of Gramsci was naturally very different. No
distant political determinant was at work in his theorisations
of the relationship between state and civil society. The
difficulties and contradictions of his texts were rather a
reflection of the impediments of his imprisonment. There was,
however, a philosophical determinant of his tendency to distend
the frontiers of the state. For Gramsci did not produce the idea
of an indefinite extension of the state as a political structure
from nowhere. He took it, quite directly, from Benedetto Croce.
No less than four times in the Prison Notebooks, Gramsci
cited Croce’s view that the ‘State’ was a higher entity, not to
be identified with mere empirical government, that could at
times find its real expression in what might seem institutions
or arenas of civil society. ‘Croce goes so far as to assert that
the true “State”, that is the directing force in the historical
process, is sometimes to be found not where it is usually
believed to be, in the State as juridically defined, but often
in “private” forces, and sometimes in so-called revolutionaries.
This proposition of Croce’s is very important for a
comprehension of his conception of history and politics.’30 The
metaphysical character of Croce’s conception is, of course,
manifest: the idea of a numinous essence of the state, floating
above mere juridical or institutional appearances, was a
typically Hegelian heritage. Its reproduction by a strenuously
anti-Hegelian school within Western Marxism has a peculiar
irony.
This speculative and anti-scientific legacy of
Croce’s thought undoubtedly had its effects on Gramsci’s work.
An example of the vagaries for which it was responsible is a
text from the Notebooks in which Gramsci entertains the
idea that parliament might, in certain cases, not be part of the
state at all.31 The misguided direction in which the
Crocean fancy led is evident in all those passages of Gramsci’s
writings which assert or suggest a dissolution of the boundaries
between state and civil society. At the same time, however, it
is noticeable that wherever Gramsci had to speak directly of the
experience of fascism in Italy, he never mistook the
significance of the delimitation between the two. For fascism
precisely tended to suppress this boundary in practice, and once
political concerns proper were primary, Gramsci had no
difficulty in registering historical realities. ‘With the events
of 1924–6, when all political parties were suppressed’, he
wrote, ‘the coincidence of pays réel and pays légal was
henceforward proclaimed in Italy, because civil society in all
its forms was now integrated into a single party-political
organisation of the State.’32 Gramsci had no
illusions about the significance of the innovations imposed by
the counterrevolutionary dictatorship of which he was a victim.
‘The contemporary dictatorships juridically abolish even the
modern forms of autonomy’ of the subordinate classes, he
wrote—such as ‘parties, trade unions, cultural associations’—and
so ‘seek to incorporate them into the activity of the State: the
legal centralisation of all national life in the hands of a
ruling group that is now “totalitarian”.’33 Thus
whatever analytic errors were due to Croce’s influence in
Gramsci’s texts, the aberration of equating fascist and
parliamentary forms of the capitalist state was not among them.
The oscillations in Gramsci’s usage of his central
terms have been noted: he never unambiguously committed himself
to any of them. It can, nevertheless, be said that his third
version of the relationship between state and civil
society—identification—is a reminder that in his prison writings
there is no comprehensive comparison of bourgeois democracy and
fascism. The problem of the specific difference between the two
remains in a sense unresolved in them, which is partly why
Gramsci—victim of a police dictatorship in a relatively backward
European country—could paradoxically appear after the Second
World War as the theorist par excellence of the
parliamentary state of the advanced capitalist countries. The
importance of an operational distinction between state and civil
society is posed with particular urgency, as we have seen, for
any such comparative analysis. Gramsci’s third version in the
end tends to suppress the central theoretical problem of his
first two versions. The Gordian knot of the relationship between
state and civil society in Western social formations, as
distinct from Tsarist Russia, is cut by peremptorily decreeing
that the state is coextensive with the social formation anyway.
The problem, however, remains, and the greater number of
Gramsci’s texts devoted to exploring his first equations testify
to his undiminished consciousness of it.
3
ASYMMETRY
Keeping for the moment to the terms of the Prison
Notebooks,1 it has been seen that the key
distribution, which eludes each of Gramsci’s successive
versions, although they miss it from different directions, is an
asymmetry between civil society and the state in the West:
coercion is located in the one, consent is located in both. This
‘topological’ answer, however, itself poses a further and deeper
problem. Beyond their distribution, what is the interrelation or
connexion between consent and coercion in the structure of
bourgeois class power in metropolitan capitalism? The workings
of bourgeois democracy appear to justify the idea that advanced
capitalism fundamentally rests on the consent of the working
class to it. In fact, acceptance of this conception is the
cornerstone of the strategy of the ‘parliamentary road to
socialism’, along which progress can be measured by the
conversion of the proletariat to the prospect of socialism,
until an arithmetical majority is achieved, whereupon the rule
of the parliamentary system makes the enactment of socialism
painlessly possible. The idea that the power of capital
essentially or exclusively takes the form of cultural hegemony
in the West is a classical tenet of reformism. This is the
involuntary temptation that lurks in some of Gramsci’s notes. Is
it truly banished by his alternative assertion that the hegemony
of the Western bourgeoisie is a combination of consent and
coercion? There is no doubt that this is an improvement, but the
relationship between the two terms cannot be grasped by their
mere conjunction or addition. Yet within Gramsci’s framework
everything depends on an accurate calibration of precisely this
relation. How should it be conceived, theoretically?
No adequate answer to the question can be presented
here. For a serious solution of it is only possible through
historical enquiry. No philological commentary, or theoretical
fiat, can settle the difficult problems of bourgeois class power
in the West. A directly substantive and comparative
investigation of the actual political systems of the major
imperialist countries in the twentieth century can alone
establish the real structures of the rule of capital. All that
can be attempted here is to advance certain critical suggestions
within the textual limits of Gramsci’s discourse. Their
verification necessarily remains subject to the ordinary
disciplines of scientific study.
To formulate a preliminary response, we can turn to
a phrase of Gramsci himself. In the first notebook he composed
in prison, he referred in passing to ‘forms of mixed struggle’
that were ‘fundamentally military and preponderantly political’
in character—noting at the same time that ‘every political
struggle always has a military substratum’.2 The
paradoxical juxtaposition and distinction of ‘fundamental’ and
‘preponderant’ to describe the relationship between two forms of
struggle, provides a formula that can be adapted for a more
adequate account of the dispositions of bourgeois class power in
advanced capitalism. The Althusserian tradition was later to
codify the same duality with its distinction between
‘determinant’ and ‘dominant’—taken not from Gramsci, but from
Marx. In analysing the contemporary social formations of the
West, we can substitute ‘coercion’ or ‘repression’ for Gramsci’s
‘military struggle’—as the mode of class rule enforced by
violence; ‘culture’ or ‘ideology’ for his ‘political
struggle’—as the mode of class rule secured by consent. It is
then possible to capture something like the real nature of the
relationship between the two variables by which Gramsci was
haunted. If we revert to Gramsci’s original problematic, the
normal structure of capitalist political power in
bourgeois-democratic states is in effect simultaneously and
indivisibly dominated by culture and determined by coercion. To
deny the ‘preponderant’ or dominant role of culture in the
contemporary bourgeois power system is to liquidate the most
salient immediate difference between Western parliamentarism and
Russian absolutism, and to reduce the former to a myth. The fact
is that this cultural domination is embodied in certain
irrefutably concrete institutions: regular elections, civic
freedoms, rights of assembly—all of which exist in the West and
none of which directly threaten the class power of capital.3 The
day-to-day system of bourgeois rule is thus based on the consent
of the masses, in the form of the ideological belief that they
exercise self-government in the representative state. At the
same time, however, to forget the ‘fundamental’ or determinant
role of violence within the power structure of contemporary
capitalism in the final instance is to regress to reformism, in
the illusion that an electoral majority can legislate socialism
peacefully from a parliament.
An analogy may serve to illuminate the relationship
in question—provided its limits (those of any analogy) are kept
in mind. A classical monetary system was constituted from two
distinct media of exchange: paper and gold.4 It was
not a summation of these two forms, for the value of fiduciary
issue which circulated every day and maintained the system under
normal conditions was dependent on the quantum of metal in the
bank reserves at any given moment, despite the fact that this
metal was virtually absent from the system as a medium of
exchange. Only the paper, not the gold, appeared within
circulation, yet the paper was in the final instance determined
by the gold, without which it ceased to be sound currency.
Crisis conditions, moreover, would necessarily trigger a sudden
reversion of the total system to the metal which lay invisibly
behind it: a collapse of credit infallibly produced a rush to
gold.5 In the political system, a similar structural
(non-additive and non-transitive) relationship between ideology
and repression—consent and coercion—prevails. The normal
conditions of ideological subordination of the masses—the
day-to-day routines of a parliamentary democracy—are themselves
constituted by a silent, absent force which gives them their
currency: the monopoly of legitimate violence by the state.
Deprived of this, the system of cultural control would be
instantly fragile, since the limits of possible actions against
it would disappear.6 With it, the system is immensely
powerful—so powerful that it can, paradoxically, do ‘without’
it: in effect, violence may normally scarcely appear within the
bounds of the system at all.
In the most tranquil democracies today, the army may
remain invisible in its barracks, the police appear
uncontentious on its beat. The analogy holds too in another
respect. Just as gold as a material substratum of paper is
itself a convention that needs acceptance as a medium of
exchange, so repression as a guarantor of ideology itself
depends on the assent of those who are trained to exercise it.
Given this critical proviso, however, the ‘fundamental’ resort
of bourgeois class power, beneath the ‘preponderant’ cusp of
culture in a parliamentary system, remains coercion.
For historically, and this is the most essential
point of all, the development of any revolutionary crisis
necessarily displaces the dominance within the bourgeois power
structure from ideology to violence. Coercion becomes both
determinant and dominant in the supreme crisis, and the army
inevitably occupies the front of the stage in any class struggle
against the prospect of a real inauguration of socialism.
Capitalist power can in this sense be regarded as a topological
system with a ‘mobile’ centre: in any crisis, an objective
redeployment occurs, and capital re-concentrates from its
representative into its repressive apparatuses. The fact that
the subjectivity of leading cadres of these apparatuses in
Western countries today may remain innocent of any such scenario
is not proof of their constitutional neutrality, but merely of
the remoteness of the prospect to them. In fact, any
revolutionary crisis within an advanced capitalist country must
inevitably produce a reversion to the ultimate determinant of
the power system: force. This is a law of capitalism, which it
cannot violate, on pain of death. It is the rule of the end-game
situation.
It should now be clear why Gramsci’s concept of
hegemony, for all its merits as a first theoretical
‘divining-rod’ of the uncharted specificity of Western social
formations,7 contains a potential political danger.
It has been seen how the term, which originated in Russia to
define the relationship between the proletariat and peasantry in
a bourgeois revolution, was transferred by Gramsci to describe
the relationship between the bourgeoisie and proletariat in a
consolidated capitalist order in Western Europe. The common
thread which permitted this extension was the consensual tenor
of the idea of hegemony. Used in Russia to denote the persuasive
nature of the influence the working class should seek to win
over the peasantry, as opposed to the coercive nature of the
struggle to overthrow Tsarism, it was then applied by Gramsci to
the forms of consent to its rule won by the bourgeoisie from the
working class in the West. The service which he rendered to
Marxism, by focusing so centrally on the—hitherto evaded—problem
of the consensual legitimacy of parliamentary institutions in
Western Europe, was a solitary and signal one. At the same time,
however, the risks attendant on the new extension of the concept
of hegemony were soon evident in his writings.
For whereas in Russia the term could exhaust the
relationship between proletariat and peasantry, since the former
was an alliance between non-antagonistic classes, the same could
never be true in, say, Italy or France of the relationship
between bourgeoisie and proletariat—inherently a conflict
between antagonistic classes, founded on two adversary positions
within the capitalist mode of production. In other words,
capitalist rule in the West necessarily comprised coercion as
well as consent. Gramsci’s awareness of this was expressed in
the numerous formulations in his notebooks which refer to the
combinations between the two. But, as we have seen, these never
succeed in locating definitely or precisely either the position
or the interconnexion of repression and ideology within the
power structure of advanced capitalism. Moreover, in so far as
Gramsci at times suggested that consent primarily pertained to
civil society, and civil society possessed primacy over the
state, he allowed the conclusion that bourgeois class power was
primarily consensual. In this form, the idea of hegemony tends
to accredit the notion that the dominant mode of bourgeois power
in the West—‘culture’—is also the determinant mode, either by
suppressing the latter or fusing the modes two together. It
thereby omits the unappealable role in the last instance of
force.
However, Gramsci’s use of the term hegemony was not,
of course, confined to the bourgeoisie as a social class. He
also employed it to trace the paths of ascent of the proletariat
in the West. A further shift in the evolution of the concept was
involved here. The prescriptive relationship
proletariat/peasantry had plausibly been equated with a cultural
ascendancy; the actual relationship bourgeoisie/proletariat
certainly included a cultural ascendancy, although it could not
be equated or reduced to it; but could the relationship
proletariat/bourgeoisie be said in any sense to betoken or
promise a cultural ascendancy? Many admirers of Gramsci have
thought so. Indeed, it has often been held that his most
original and powerful single thesis was precisely the idea that
the working class can be hegemonic culturally before becoming
the ruling class politically, within a capitalist social
formation. Official interpretations of Gramsci have, in
particular, been keyed to such a prospect. The text from the Prison
Notebooksto which reference is customarily made does not,
however, assert this. In it, Gramsci wrote: ‘A social group is
dominant over enemy groups which it tends to “liquidate” or
subject with armed force, and is directive over affinal and
allied groups. A social group can and indeed must be directive
before conquering governmental power (this is one of the main
conditions for the conquest of power itself); afterwards, when
it exercises power and keeps it firmly in its grasp, it becomes
dominant but also continues to be “directive”.’8 Gramsci
here carefully distinguishes the necessity for coercion of enemy
classes from the consensual direction of allied classes. The
‘hegemonic activity’ which ‘can and must be exercised before the
assumption of power’ is related in this context only to the
problem of the alliances of the working class with other
exploited and oppressed groups; it is not a claim to hegemony
over the whole of society, or the ruling class itself, by
definition impossible at this stage.
It is true, however, that any unwary reader can be
led to misconstrue this passage, where Gramsci is actually on
safe ground, by ambiguities in his use of the term hegemony
elsewhere. We shall see why shortly. For the moment, what is
important to recall is the familiar Marxist tenet that the
working class under capitalism is inherently incapable of being
the culturally dominant class, because it is structurally
expropriated by its class position from some of the essential
means of cultural production (education, tradition, leisure)—in
contrast to the bourgeoisie of the Enlightenment, which could
generate its own superior culture within the framework of the
Ancien Régime. Not only this, but even after a socialist
revolution—the conquest of political power by the
proletariat—the culturally dominant class remains the
bourgeoisie in certain respects (not all—habits more than ideas)
and for a certain time (in principle shorter with each
revolution), as Lenin and Trotsky emphasised in different
contexts.9 Gramsci was intermittently conscious of
this too.10 So long, however, as the lack of
structural correspondence between the positions of the bourgeois
class within feudal society and the working class within
capitalist society was not constantly registered, the risk of a
theoretical slide from one to the other was always potentially
present in the common use of the term hegemony for them. The
more than occasional assimilation of the bourgeois and
proletarian revolutions in his writings on Jacobinism
demonstrates that Gramsci was not immune to this confusion. The
result was to permit later codifications of his thought to link
his two extensions of the concept of hegemony into a classically
reformist syllogism. For once bourgeois power in the West is
primarily attributed to cultural hegemony, the acquisition of
this hegemony would mean effective assumption by the working
class of the ‘direction of society’ without the seizure and
transformation of state power, in a painless transition to
socialism: in other words, a typical idea of Fabianism. Gramsci
himself, of course, never drew this conclusion. But in the
scattered letter of his texts, it was not an entirely arbitrary
interpolation either.
How was it possible for Gramsci, a communist
militant with a past of unwavering—indeed undue—political
hostility to reformism, to leave a legacy of such ambiguity? The
answer must be sought in the framework of reference within which
he wrote. The theory and practice of the Third International,
from the inception of its history with Lenin to the
incarceration of Gramsci, had been saturated with emphasis on
the historical necessity of violence in the destruction and
construction of states. The dictatorship of the proletariat,
after the armed overthrow of the bourgeois state apparatus, was
the touchstone —tirelessly proclaimed in every official
document—of the Marxism of the Comintern. Gramsci never
questioned these principles. On the contrary, when he started
his theoretical explorations in prison, he seems to have taken
them so much for granted that they scarcely ever figure directly
in his discourse at all. They form as it were the familiar
acquisition, which no longer needed reiteration, in an
intellectual enterprise whose energies were concentrated
elsewhere—on the discovery of the unfamiliar. But in the absence
of any possibility of integrated composition, denied him in
prison, Gramsci’s intent pursuit of new themes and ideas exposed
him to the persistent risk of temporarily losing sight of older
verities, and so of neglecting or mistaking the relationship
between the two. The problem of consent, which forms the real
fulcrum of his work, is the critical point of this process.
Gramsci was acutely aware of the novelty and difficulty for
Marxist theory of the phenomenon of institutionalised popular
consent to capital in the West—hitherto regularly evaded or
repressed within the Comintern tradition. He therefore focussed
all the powers of his intelligence on it. In doing so, he never
intended to deny or rescind the classical axioms of that
tradition on the inevitable role of social coercion within any
great historical transformation, so long as classes subsisted.
His objective was, in one of his phrases, to ‘complement’
treatment of the one with an exploration of the other.
The premises and aims that produced the selective
lens of his work can be seen with particular clarity in his
commentaries on Croce. The importance of Croce for Gramsci’s
whole programme in prison is well known. His remarks on Croce’s
historical studies are therefore especially revealing. Gramsci
repeatedly and expressly criticised Croce for his unilateral
exaltation of the consensual and moral, and concomitant evasion
of the military and coercive, moments in European history. ‘In
his two recent books, The History of Italy and The
History of Europe, it is precisely the moments of force, of
struggle, of misery that are omitted … Is it an accident, or is
it tendentiously, that Croce starts his narratives from 1815 and
1871 respectively? In other words, that he excludes the moment
of struggle, the moment in which conflicting forces are formed,
assembled and deployed, the moment in which one system of social
relations dissolves and another is forged in fire and steel, the
moment in which one system of social relations disintegrates and
declines while another emerges and affirms itself—and instead
placidly assumes the moment of cultural or ethico-political
expansion to be all history?’11
The terse terms of Gramsci’s summary of the
political bent of Crocean idealist historiography show how
naturally he assumed the classical canons of revolutionary
Marxism. ‘Ethico-political history is an arbitrary and
mechanical hypostasis of the moment of hegemony, of political
direction, of consent, in the life and in the development of the
State and of civil society.’12 Yet at the same time,
Gramsci regarded Croce as a superior thinker to Gentile, who
committed the opposite hypostasis—a fetishism of force and
state—in his philosophy of actualism. ‘For Gentile, history is
exclusively history of the State. For Croce it is rather
“ethico-political”, that is Croce wants to preserve a
distinction between civil society and political society, between
hegemony and dictatorship; great intellectuals exercise
hegemony, which presupposes a certain collaboration, in other
words an active and voluntary (free) consent, in a
liberal-democratic order. Gentile poses the
economico-corporative phase as the ethical phase in the act of
history: hegemony and dictatorship are indistinguishable, force
is consent without further ado: political society cannot be
differentiated from civil society: the State alone exists, and
naturally as the government State.’13
For in fact, with all its exaggeration, it was
precisely Croce’s emphasis on the role of culture and the
significance of consent that was the reason for the pre-eminent
theoretical status Gramsci attributed to him. To Gramsci, these
represented a philosophical exordium or equivalent to the
doctrine of hegemony within historical materialism. ‘Croce’s
thought should therefore at the very least be appreciated as an
instrumental value, for it can be said that he has energetically
drawn attention to the importance of the phenomena of culture
and of thought in the development of history, of the function of
major intellectuals in the organic life of civil society and the
State, of the moment of hegemony and consent in the necessary
form of any concrete historical bloc.’14 Thus Croce
could even be compared by Gramsci to Lenin, as joint authors of
the notion of hegemony: ‘Contemporaneously with Croce, the
greatest modern theorist of Marxism has, on the terrain of
political organisation and struggle, and in political
terminology, revalued—in opposition to diverse “economist”
tendencies—the doctrine of hegemony as the complement to the
theory of the State as coercion.’15
In his final assessment, Gramsci was so seized with
the importance of Croce’s ‘ethico-political history’ that he
could argue that Marxism as a philosophy could only achieve a
modern renewal through a critique and integration of Croce,
comparable to Marx’s assimilation and supersession of Hegel. In
his famous dictum: ‘It is necessary for us to repeat today the
same reduction of Croce’s philosophy as the first theorists of
Marxism accomplished for Hegel’s philosophy. This is the sole
historically fecund way of achieving an adequate renewal of
Marxism, of elevating its conceptions—perforce “vulgarised” in
immediate practical life—to the heights necessary for it to be
able to resolve the more complex tasks of the present
development of struggle—that is, the creation of an integral new
culture, which would have the popular characteristics of the
Protestant Reformation and the French Enlightenment, and the
classical traits of Greek culture and of the Italian
Renaissance, a culture which would—in Carducci’s
phrase—synthesise Maximilien Robespierre and Immanuel Kant,
politics and philosophy in a single dialectical unity, belonging
to a social group that was not merely French or German, but
European and universal. The heritage of German classical
philosophy must not merely be inventoried, but made to live
actively again. For that, it is necessary to come to terms with
the philosophy of Croce.’16 The curvature of
Gramsci’s comments on Croce thus traces very accurately the way
in which he presumed the gains of the Comintern tradition;
preferred to explore what it had relatively neglected; and ended
by overstating the case for a bourgeois tradition that had not
done so, whose weaknesses he had started by criticizing.
The inadvertent movement of thought visible in these
texts on Croce was responsible for the paradoxes of Gramsci’s
theorisation of hegemony. To understand them, it is necessary to
separate the objective logic of Gramsci’s terms from his
subjective political stance as a whole. For the involuntary
concatenation of the one yielded results in profound
contradiction with the inmost will of the other. The disjuncture
that silently developed in Gramsci’s notebooks was due, of
course, to his inability to write any ordinary statement of his
overall views. In this sense, fascist censorship, while not
preventing his research, exacted an undeniable toll on it.
Throughout his imprisonment, Gramsci wrestled with the relations
between coercion and consent in the advanced capitalist
societies of the West. But because he could never produce a
unitary theory of the two—which would necessarily have had to
take the form of a direct and comprehensive survey of the
intricate institutional patterns of bourgeois power, in either
their parliamentary or their fascist variants—an unwitting list
gradually edged his texts towards the pole of consent, at the
expense of that of coercion.
The conceptual slippage which results in Gramsci’s
work can be compared with that which marks the thought of his
celebrated ancestor and inspiration in prison. For Machiavelli,
from whom Gramsci took so many themes, had also set out to
analyse the dual forms of the Centaur—half-man,
half-beast—symbol of the hybrid of compulsion and consent by
which men were always governed. In Machiavelli’s work, however,
the slide occurred in exactly the opposite direction. Ostensibly
concerned with ‘arms’ and ‘laws’, coercion and consent, his
actual discourse slipped unstoppably towards ‘force’ and
‘fraud’—in other words, the animal component of power alone.17 The
result was the rhetoric of repression later generations were to
call Machiavellianism. Gramsci adopted Machiavelli’s myth of the
Centaur as the emblematic motto of his research: but where
Machiavelli had effectively collapsed consent into coercion, in
Gramsci coercion was progressively eclipsed by consent. The
Prince and The Modern Princeare in this sense
distorting mirrors of each other. There is an inverse
correspondence between the failings of the two.
We may now recollect the famous comparison between
East and West in the Prison Notebooks, with which we
started. Gramsci defined the contrast between the two in terms
of the relative position occupied by state and civil society in
each. In Russia, the state was ‘everything’, while civil society
was ‘primordial and gelatinous’. In Western Europe, on the
contrary, the state was merely an ‘outer ditch’, while civil
society was a ‘powerful system of fortresses and earthworks’
whose complex structures could withstand seismic political or
economic crises for the state. These texts of Gramsci, which
seek to capture the strategic differences between Russia and the
West for a socialist revolution, set him apart from his
contemporaries. In the immediate aftermath of the October
Revolution, there were many socialists in Central and Western
Europe who sensed that the local conditions in which they had to
fight were far from those which had obtained in Russia, and who
initially said so.18 None, however, provided any
coherent analysis or serious explanation of the fateful
divergence in the historical experience of the European working
class of the time. By the end of the twenties, the problem of
the contrast between Russia and the West had effectively
disappeared from Marxist debate. With the Stalinisation of the
Comintern, and the institutionalisation of what was presented as
an official Leninism within it, the example of the USSR became
the mandatory paradigm for all issues of revolutionary theory
and practice to militants across Europe. Gramsci was unique
among Communists in persisting, at the nadir of the defeats of
the thirties, to see that Russian experience could not be merely
repeated in the West, and in trying to understand why. No other
thinker in the European working class movement has to this day
addressed himself so deeply or centrally to the problem of the
specificity of a socialist revolution in the West.
Yet, for all the intensity and originality of his
enquiry, Gramsci never finally succeeded in arriving at an
adequate Marxist account of the distinction between East and
West. The image from the compass itself proved, in the end, a
snare. For a simple geographical opposition includes by
definition an unproblematic comparability of the two terms.
Transferred to social formations, however, it implies something
that can never be taken for granted: that there is a
straightforward historical comparability between them. In other
words, the terms East and West assume that the social formations
on each side of the divide exist in the same temporality, and
can therefore be read off against each other as variations of a
common category. It is this unspoken presupposition which lies
behind the central texts of Gramsci’s notebooks. His whole
contrast between Russia and Western Europe revolves on the
difference in the relationship between state and civil society
in the two zones: its unexamined premise is that the state is
the same type of object in both. But this assumption was just
what needed to be questioned.
For, in fact, there was no initial unity to found a
simple distinction between East and West of the sort that
Gramsci was seeking. In its nature and structure, the Tsarism of
Nicholas II was a specifically ‘Eastern’ variant of a feudal
state, whose Western counterparts—the Absolute monarchies of
France or England, Spain or Sweden—had died out centuries
before.19 In other words, the constant comparison
between the Russian and Western States was a paralogism, unless
the differential historical time of each was specified. A prior
comprehension of the uneven development of European feudalism
was thus a necessary preamble to a Marxist definition of the
Tsarist state which was finally destroyed by the first socialist
revolution. For it alone could yield the theoretical concept of
absolutism that would allow socialist militants to see the
enormous gulf between the Russian autocracy and the capitalist
states with which they were confronted in the West (and whose
theoretical concept had to be constructed separately).
The representative state which had gradually emerged
in Western Europe, North America and Japan, after the complex
chain of bourgeois revolutions whose final episodes dated only
from the late nineteenth century, was still a largely uncharted
political object for Marxists when the Bolshevik Revolution
occurred. In the early years of the Third International, the
light of October blinded many revolutionaries outside Russia to
the nature of their national enemy altogether. Those who
remained lucid initially tried to adapt to their indigenous
realities without relinquishing their fidelity to the cause of
the Russian Revolution, by evoking the difference between East
and West. They soon desisted. Gramsci alone, isolated from the
Comintern, took up this path again and pursued it with matchless
courage in prison. But so long as the simultaneity of its terms
was assumed, the conundrum of the difference was ultimately
unanswerable. The failure to produce a focussed comparative
analysis of the respective types of state and structures of
power in Russia and the West was in no way peculiar to Gramsci.
From the other side of the continental divide, no Bolshevik
leader succeeded in developing a coherent theory of it either.
The true contrast between the Tsarist and the Western states
eluded each from opposite ends. Thus Lenin never mistook the
class character of Tsarism: he always expressly insisted,
against Menshevik opponents, that Russian absolutism was a
feudal state machine.20 Yet he also never adequately
or systematically contrasted the parliamentary states of the
West with the autocratic state in the East. There is no direct
theory of bourgeois democracy anywhere in his writings. Gramsci,
on the other hand, was intensely conscious of the novelty of the
capitalist state in the West, as an object for Marxist analysis
and adversary for Marxist strategy, and of the integrity of
representative institutions to its normal operation. He,
however, never perceived that the absolutism in Russia with
which he contrasted it was a feudal state—a political edifice of
a different order altogether. In the no man’s land between the
thought of the two, revolutionary socialism missed a theoretical
junction critical for its future in Europe.
In the case of Gramsci, his inability to grasp the
historical disjuncture concealed by the geographical form of his
unity-distinction left its determinate effects on his theory of
bourgeois power in the West. Gramsci, as we have seen, was
constantly aware of the twin character of this power, but he
never succeeded in giving it a stable formulation. Thus his
passages on the distinction between East and West all suffer
from the same flaw; their ultimate logic is always to tend to
revert to the simple schema of an opposition between ‘hegemony’
(consent) in the West and ‘dictatorship’ (coercion) in the East:
parliamentarism versus Tsarism. In Tsarist Russia, ‘there was no
legal political freedom, nor any religious freedom either’,21 within
a state that left no autonomy to civil society. In Republican
France, by contrast, ‘the parliamentary regime realised the
permanent hegemony of the urban class over the population as a
whole’ by means of ‘rule by permanently organised consent’, in
which ‘the organisation of consent is left to private
initiatives, and is thus moral or ethical in character, because
it is in one way or another “voluntarily” given’.22 The
weakness of Gramsci’s counterposition was not so much its
overestimation of the ideological claims of the Tsarist state
within the Russian social formation—which was indeed far more
extensive than that of any contemporary Western state, if not as
absolute as Gramsci’s attribution to it of a command over
‘everything’. It was its underestimation of the specificity and
stability of the repressive machinery of army and police, and
its functional relationship to the representative machinery of
suffrage and parliament, within the Western state.
Strangely, it was not Gramsci but his comrade and
antagonist Amadeo Bordiga who was to formulate the true nature
of the distinction between East and West, although he never
theorised it into any cogent political practice. At the fateful
Sixth Plenum of the Executive Committee of the Communist
International, in February–March 1926, Bordiga—by now isolated
and suspected within his own party—confronted Stalin and
Bukharin for the final time. In a remarkable speech to the
Plenum, he said:
We have in the International only one party that has
achieved revolutionary victory—the Bolshevik Party. They say
that we should therefore take the road which led the Russian
party to success. This is perfectly true, but it remains
insufficient. The fact is that the Russian party fought under
special conditions, in a country where the bourgeois-liberal
revolution had not yet been accomplished and the feudal
aristocracy had not yet been defeated by the capitalist
bourgeoisie. Between the fall of the feudal autocracy and the
seizure of power by the working class lay too short a period for
there to be any comparison with the development which the
proletariat will have to accomplish in other countries. For
there was no time to build a bourgeois State machine on the
ruins of the Tsarist feudal apparatus. Russian development does
not provide us with an experience of how the proletariat can
overthrow a liberal-parliamentary capitalist State that has
existed for many years and possesses the ability to defend
itself. We, however, must know how to attack a modern
bourgeois-democratic State that on the one hand has its own
means of ideologically mobilizing and corrupting the
proletariat, and on the other can defend itself on the terrain
of armed struggle with greater efficacy than could the Tsarist
autocracy. This problem never arose in the history of the
Russian Communist Party.23
Here the real opposition between Russia and the West
emerges clearly and unambiguously: feudal autocracy against
bourgeois democracy. The accuracy of Bordiga’s formulation
allowed him to grasp the essential twin character of the
capitalist state: it was stronger than the Tsarist state,
because it rested not only on the consent of the masses, but
also on a superior repressive apparatus. In other words, it is
not the mere ‘extent’ of the state that defines its location in
the structure of power (what Gramsci elsewhere called
‘statolatry’), but also its efficacy. The repressive apparatus
of any modern capitalist state is inherently superior to that of
Tsarism, for two reasons. Firstly, because the Western social
formations are much more industrially advanced, and this
technology is reflected in the apparatus of violence itself.
Secondly, because the masses typically consent to this state in
the belief that they exercise government over it. It therefore
possesses a popular legitimacy of a far more reliable character
for the exercise of this repression than did Tsarism in its
decline, reflected in the greater discipline and loyalty of its
troops and police—juridically the servants, not of an
irresponsible autocrat, but of an elected assembly. The keys to
the power of the capitalist state in the West lie in this
conjoined superiority.
4
CONTEXTS
We can now, in conclusion, review Gramsci’s
strategic doctrine—in other words, the political perspectives
that he deduced from his theoretical analysis of the nature of
bourgeois rule in the West. What were the lessons of the
morphology of capitalist hegemony, as he sought to reconstruct
it in prison, for the working class movement? What was the
political crux of the problem of the bourgeois state for a
Western strategy of the proletarian revolution? Gramsci, as a
theorist and a militant, never separated the two. His solution
to the cipher of success in the West was, as we have seen, a
‘war of position’. What was the real meaning and effect of this
formula?
To understand Gramsci’s strategic theory, it is
necessary to retrace the decisive original polemic within the
European workers’ movement to which it was a hidden, ulterior
response. With the victory of the Russian Revolution, and the
collapse of the Hohenzollern and Habsburg empires in central
Europe, key theorists of German communism came to believe that,
in the aftermath of the First World War, the seizure of power by
the proletariat was on the immediate agenda in every imperialist
country, because the world had now definitively entered the
historical epoch of the socialist revolution. This belief was
most fully and forcefully expressed by Georg Lukács, then a
leading member of the exiled Hungarian Communist Party, writing
in the German-language theoretical review Kommunismus in
Vienna. For Lukács, there was now a ‘universal actuality of the
proletarian revolution’, determined by the general stage of the
development of capitalism, which was henceforward in mortal
crisis.
‘This means that the actuality of the revolution is
no longer only a world-historical horizon arching over the
self-liberating working class, but that revolution is already on
its agenda … The actuality of the revolution provides the
key-note of the whole epoch.’1
This fusion—confusion—between the theoretical
concepts of historical epoch and historical conjuncture allowed
Lukács and prominent colleagues in the KPD such as Thalheimer
and Frölich to ignore the problem of the concrete preconditions
for a revolutionary situation by abstractly affirming the
revolutionary character of the time itself. On this premise,
they went on to argue for a novel tactic: the Teilaktion or
‘partial’ armed action against the capitalist state.
Within the ranks of the Second International,
Bernstein and co-thinkers had maintained the possibility of
‘partial’ ameliorations of capitalism by means of parliamentary
reforms, that would in a gradual process of evolution eventually
lead to the peaceful completion of socialism. The illusion that
the inherent unity of the capitalist state could be divided or
attained by successive partial measures, slowly transforming its
class character, had been a traditional prerogative of
reformism. There now, however, emerged an adventurist version of
the same error in the Third International. For in 1920–21,
Thalheimer, Frölich, Lukács and others theorised putschist
‘partial actions’ as a series of armed attacks against the
bourgeois state, limited in scope yet constant in tempo. In the
words of Kommunismus: ‘The principal characteristic of
the present period of the revolution lies in this, that we are
now compelled to conduct even partial battles, including
economic ones, with the instrumentalities of the final battle’,
above all ‘armed insurrection’.2
This was the theory of the ‘revolutionary
offensive’. Since the epoch was revolutionary, the only correct
strategy was an offensive one, to be mounted in a series of
repeated armed blows against the capitalist state. These should
be undertaken even if the working class was not in an
immediately revolutionary mood: they would then precisely serve
to ‘awaken’ the proletariat from its reformist torpor. Lukács
provided the most sophisticated justification of these
adventures. He argued that partial actions were not so much
‘organisational measures by which the Communist Party could
seize State power’ as ‘autonomous and active initiatives of the
KPD to overcome the ideological crisis and menshevik lethargy of
the proletariat, and standstill of revolutionary development’.3 For
Lukács, the rationale of the Teilaktionen was thus not
their objective aims, but their subjective impact on the
consciousness of the working class. ‘If revolutionary
development is not to run the risk of stagnation, another
outcome must be found: the action of the KPD in an offensive. An
offensive signifies: the independent action of the party at the
right moment with the right slogan, to awaken the proletarian
masses from their inertia, to wrest them away from their
menshevik leadership by action (in other words organisationally
and not merely ideologically), and thereby to cut the knot of
the ideological crisis of the proletariat with the sword of the
deed.’4
The fate of these pronouncements was rapidly settled
by the lesson of events themselves. The radical misunderstanding
of the integral unity of capitalist state power, and the
necessarily all-or-nothing character of any insurrection against
it, naturally led to disaster in Central Germany. In March 1921,
the KPD launched its much vaunted offensive against the Prussian
state government, by falling into the trap of a badly prepared
rising against a preventive police occupation of the
Mansfeld–Merseburg area. In the absence of any spontaneous
working class resistance, the KPD desperately resorted to
dynamiting actions designed to provoke police bombardments;
seizure of factories and street fighting followed; wandering
guerrilla bands submerged any discipline in anarchic forays
through the countryside. For a week, heavy fighting raged in
Central Germany between KPD militants and the police and
Reichswehr units mobilised to suppress them. The result was a
foregone conclusion. Isolated from the rest of the German
proletariat, bewildered and dislocated by the arbitrary
character of the action, hopelessly outnumbered by the
concentration of Reichswehr troops in the Merseburg–Halle
region, the vanguard flung into this confrontation with the full
might of the army was routed. A drastic wave of repression
succeeded the March Action. Some 4,000 militants were sentenced
to prison, and the KPD received its quietus in Prussian Saxony.
Not only was the objective of state power never achieved, but
the subjective impact on the German working class and the KPD
itself was calamitous. Far from rousing the proletariat from its
‘menshevik lethargy’, the March Action demoralised and
disillusioned it. The vanguard zone of the Merseburg mines
relapsed into a desert of apolitical backwardness. Worse still,
the KPD never wholly regained the trust of wide sections of the
German proletariat thereafter. Its membership had been 350,000
before the March offensive: within a few weeks of the disaster,
it had plummeted to half that number. It never attained
comparable levels of strength again in the Weimar Republic.
The adventurism of the KPD in 1921 was condemned by
the Third World Congress of the Comintern. Lenin wrote a famous
letter to the German Party, demolishing the justifications for
it. Trotsky denounced the whole theory of Teilaktion: ‘A
purely mechanical conception of the proletarian revolution—which
proceeds solely from the fact that the capitalist economy
continues to decay—has led certain groups of comrades to
construe theories which are false to the core: the false theory
of an initiating minority which by its heroism shatters “the
wall of universal passivity” among the proletariat, the false
theory of uninterrupted offensives conducted by the proletarian
vanguard as a “new method” of struggle, the false theory of
partial battles which are waged by applying the methods of armed
insurrection and so on. The clearest exponent of this is the
Vienna journal Kommunismus. It is absolutely self-evident
that tactical theories of this sort have nothing in common with
Marxism. To apply them in practice is to play directly into the
hands of the bourgeoisie’s military-political leaders and their
strategy.’5 Lenin and Trotsky together waged a
resolute fight against the theory of the Teilaktion at
the Third World Congress of the Communist International, and
over German opposition it was formally repudiated by the
Comintern.
Against this background it is now possible to
reconsider Gramsci’s later attempt to define the specificity of
a Western revolutionary strategy as a ‘war of position’. For
Gramsci’s axiom was designed to represent the political
correction he believed necessary after the failure of the March
Action—which he saw as the expression of a ‘war of manoeuvre’.
His dating of the two is precise and unequivocal: ‘In the
present epoch, the war of movement occurred politically between
March 1917 and March 1921, and it was then followed by a war of
position.’6 The contrast between war of manoeuvre and
war of position, it will be remembered, was derived by analogy
from the First World War. Whereas in Russia, Gramsci wrote, the
revolution could make fast, mobile sorties against the state,
and overthrow it at great speed, in the industrialised West such
insurrectionary tactics would lead to defeat, much as the
campaign of the Tsar’s army in Galicia had done. ‘It seems to me
that Lenin understood that a change was necessary from the war
of manoeuvre applied victoriously in the East in 1917, to a war
of position which was the only possible form in the West—where,
as Krasnov observes, armies could rapidly accumulate endless
quantities of munitions, and where the social structures were of
themselves still capable of becoming heavily armed
fortifications. This is what the formula of the “united front”
seems to me to mean.’7
Gramsci’s explicit equation of ‘united front’ with
‘war of position’, which might otherwise seem baffling, becomes
immediately clear. For the United Front was the political line
adopted by the Comintern after the Third World Congress had
condemned the ‘theory of the offensive’ advocated by the KPD—a
war of manoeuvre. The strategic objective of the United Front
was to win over the masses in the West to revolutionary Marxism,
by patient organisation and skilful agitation for working-class
unity in action. Lenin, who coined the slogan ‘To the Masses’
with which the Comintern Congress of 1921 closed, expressly
emphasised its importance for a differential strategy adapted to
countries in Western Europe, in contradistinction to those in
Russia. In his speech of 1 July, replying to Terracini—the
representative of Gramsci’s own party, the PCI—he devoted his
address precisely to this theme. ‘We were victorious in Russia
not only because the undisputed majority of the working class
(during the elections of 1917 the overwhelming majority of the
workers were with us against the Mensheviks) was on our side,
but also because half the army, immediately after our seizure of
power, and nine-tenths of the peasants, in the course of some
weeks, came over to our side; we were victorious because we
took, not our agrarian programme, but that of the
Socialist-Revolutionaries and put it into effect. Our victory
lay in the fact that we carried out the Socialist-Revolutionary
Programme; that is why this victory was so easy. Is it possible
that you in the West have such illusions (about the
repeatability of this process)? It is ridiculous. Just compare
the economic conditions! … We were a small Party in Russia, but
we had with us in addition the majority of the Soviets of
Workers’ and Peasants’ Deputies throughout the country. Where do
you have that? We had with us nearly half the army, which
numbered at least 10 million men. Do you really have the
majority of the army behind you? Show me such a country! … Can
you point to any country in Europe where you could win over the
majority of the peasantry in some weeks? Perhaps Italy?
(laughter)’8
Lenin went on to stress the absolute necessity of
winning the masses in the West, before any attempt to achieve
power could be successful. This need not always imply the
creation of a vast political party: it meant that the revolution
could only be made with and by the masses themselves, who would
have to be convinced of this goal by their vanguard in an
extremely arduous preparatory phase of struggle. ‘I am certainly
not denying that revolution can be started by a very small party
and brought to a victorious conclusion. But we have to know the
methods by which the masses can be won over to our side … An
absolute majority is not always essential; but for victory and
for retaining power, what is essential is not only the majority
of the working class—I use the term working class in its West
European sense, i.e. in the sense of the industrial
proletariat—but also the majority of the working and exploited
population. Have you thought about this?’9
Gramsci was thus correct in thinking that Lenin had
formulated the policies of the United Front in 1921 to answer to
the specific problems of revolutionary strategy in Western
Europe. At the time, of course, Gramsci himself—together with
nearly the whole leadership of the PCI—had stubbornly rejected
the United Front in Italy, and had thereby facilitated the
victory of fascism, which was able to triumph over a divided
working class. From 1921 to 1924, the years when the Comintern
seriously tried to secure the implementation of United Front
tactics towards the PSI Maximalists in Italy, both Bordiga and
Gramsci refused, resisting the line of the International. By the
time Gramsci had assumed the leadership of the party in 1924,
and rallied to a policy of fidelity to the International,
fascism was already installed and the Comintern—now radically
changed in character—had largely abandoned United Front tactics
itself. Thus Gramsci’s insistence on the concept of the ‘united
front’ in his Prison Notebooksin the thirties does not
represent a renewal of his political past: on the contrary, it
marks a retrospective break with it.
For it was the contemporary situation in the
Communist International which determined the nature and
direction of the strategic texts written during Gramsci’s
imprisonment. In 1928, the famous Third Period of the Comintern
had started. Its premise was the prediction of an immediate and
catastrophic crisis of world capitalism—apparently vindicated
shortly afterwards by the Great Depression. Its axioms included
the identity of fascism and social democracy, the equivalence of
police dictatorships and bourgeois democracies, the necessity of
breakaway trade unions, and the duty of physical combat against
recalcitrant workers and labour officials. This was the epoch of
‘social-fascism’, ‘independent unions’ and ‘storming the
streets’, when left social democrats were declared the worst of
all enemies of the working class, and the advent of the Nazis to
power was greeted in advance as a welcome clarification of the
class struggle. In these years, the Communist International
plunged into an ultra-left frenzy that made the partisans of the
March Action seem restrained by comparison. In Italy itself, at
the height of Mussolini’s power, the exiled PCI declared a
revolutionary situation to be present, and the dictatorship of
the proletariat the only permissible immediate goal of struggle.
Socialists in common exile—whether maximalist or reformist—were
denounced as agents of fascism. Wave after wave of cadres were
sent into the country, only to be arrested and jailed by the
secret police, while their successes were announced in official
propaganda abroad.
Confronted with this general rush to disaster, in
which his own party was implicated, Gramsci refused its official
positions and in his search for another strategic line recalled
the United Front. The reason is now easy to see: a decade
earlier, the latter had been a riposte to adventurist
aberrations that anticipated—in a less extreme form—those of the
Third Period. The United Front acquired a new relevance for
Gramsci in the conjuncture of the early thirties. Indeed, it can
be said that it was the madness of the Third Period that finally
helped him to understand it. His emphasis on the United Front in
his Prison Notebooks thus has an unequivocal meaning. It
is a denial that the Italian masses had abandoned
social-democratic and bourgeois-democratic illusions, were in a
revolutionary ferment against fascism, or could be immediately
aroused to mobilise for the dictatorship of the proletariat in
Italy; and an insistence that these same masses must be won over
to the struggle against fascism, that working class unity could
and should be achieved by pacts of action between communists and
social democrats, and that the fall of fascism would not
automatically be the victory of socialism, because there was
always the possibility of a restoration of parliamentarism. The
United Front, in other words, signified the necessity for deep
and serious ideological-political work among the masses,
untainted by sectarianism, before the seizure of power could be
on the agenda.
At the same time, Gramsci’s strategic reorientation
in prison moved beyond the conjunctural imperatives of
peninsular resistance to fascism. It was Western Europe as a
whole, not simply Italy, that was the spatial horizon of his
political thought in these years. Similarly, it was the entire
post-war epoch after 1921, not merely the darkness of the early
thirties, that was its temporal reference. To convey the scope
of the change in political perspective which he sought to
theorise, Gramsci developed the precept of the ‘war of
position’. Valid for a complete era and an entire zone of social
struggle, the idea of a ‘war of position’ thus had a much wider
resonance than that of the tactic of the United Front once
advocated by the Comintern. Yet it was at this delicate point of
transition in Gramsci’s thought, where it sought a superior
strategic resolution, that it ran into jeopardy.
For, unknown to himself, Gramsci had an illustrious
predecessor. Karl Kautsky, in a famous debate with Rosa
Luxemburg, had in 1910 argued that the German working class in
its fight against capital should adopt an Ermattungsstrategie—a
‘strategy of attrition’. He explicitly counterposed this
conception to what he called a Niederwerfungsstrategie—a
‘strategy of overthrow’. Kautsky did not coin these terms. He
borrowed them from the terminology of the major debate over
military history then under way among scholars and soldiers in
Wilhelmine Germany. The inventor of the antithesis between Ermattungsstrategie and Niederwerfungsstrategie was
Hans Delbrück, the most original military historian of his day.
Delbrück had first presented his theory of the two types of war
in 1881, at an inaugural lecture to the University of Berlin, in
which he contrasted the campaigns of Frederick II and
Napoleon—the first as an exemplar of the protracted strategy of
attrition characteristic of the European ancien régimes, the
second as the prototype of the rapid strategy of overthrow
inaugurated by the mass popular armies of the modern epoch.10 Vehemently
contested within Prussian academic circles, for whom Delbrück’s
account of the Frederician wars verged on contumely, the theory
of the two strategies was developed by Delbrück in a series of
writings which culminated in his monumental Geschichte der
Kriegskunst im Rahmen der politischen Geschichte, spanning
the evolution of military theory and practice from antiquity to
the twentieth century.11 Successive volumes of this
work were keenly studied in the ranks of the German High Command
and those of German Social Democracy alike. Schlieffen, Chief of
the General Staff, plotted his war exercises meticulously
against Delbrück’s categories (opting eventually for a strategy
of overthrow, not of attrition, in his plan against France).
Mehring, in Die Neue Zeit, enthusiastically recommended
Delbrück’s histories to working class readers in 1908 as ‘the
most significant work produced by the historical writing of
bourgeois Germany in the new century’.12 In an essay
on them over one hundred pages long, Mehring dwelt on the
perennial validity of the opposition between attrition and
overthrow for the art of war. He ended by remarking pointedly
that Delbrück had written a work of ‘scientific research in a
field in which the modern labour movement has a more than merely
scientific interest’.13
It was Kautsky who then took the next step of
annexing Delbrück’s military concepts—without
acknowledgment—into a political debate on the strategic
perspectives of proletarian struggle against capitalism. The
occasion of his intervention was a fateful one. For it was in
order to rebut the demand by Luxemburg for the adoption of
militant mass strikes, during the SPD’s campaign for a
democratisation of the neo-feudal Prussian electoral system,
that Kautsky counterposed the necessity of a more prudent ‘war
of attrition’ by the German proletariat against its class enemy,
without the risks involved in mass strikes. The introduction of
the theory of two strategies—attrition and overthrow—was thus
the precipitate of the scission within orthodox German Marxism
before the First World War.14
The formal similarity of the opposition ‘strategy of
overthrow–strategy of attrition’, and ‘war of manoeuvre–war of
position’ is, of course, striking.15 However, the
substantive analogies between the two pairs of concepts, in the
texts of Kautsky and of Gramsci, are even more so. To support
his argument for the superiority of a strategy of attrition over
a strategy of overthrow, Kautsky evoked precisely the same
historical and geographical contrasts as Gramsci was to do in
his discussion of war of position and war of manoeuvre. The
coincidence is arresting. Thus Kautsky too fixed the
predominance of a ‘strategy of overthrow’ (Gramsci: ‘war of
manoeuvre’) from 1789 to 1870, and its supersession by a
‘strategy of attrition’ (Gramsci: ‘war of position’) from the
fall of the Commune: ‘Through a coincidence of propitious
circumstances, the revolutionaries in France during the years
1789–93 succeeded in bringing down the dominant regime in a bold
attack in a few decisive blows. This strategy of overthrow was
then the only one available for a revolutionary class, in an
absolutist police state which excluded any possibility of
building parties, or of the popular masses exercising any
constitutional influence on the government. Any strategy of
attrition would have failed because the government, confronted
with opponents who wanted to unite for a durable resistance to
it, could always cut off their possibilities of organisation or
coordination. This strategy of overthrow was still in full bloom
when our party was founded in Germany. The success of Garibaldi
in Italy and the glittering, if eventually defeated, struggles
of the Polish Insurrection immediately preceded Lassalle’s
agitation and the founding of the International. The Paris
Commune followed soon afterwards. But it was precisely the
Commune which showed that the days of a tactic of overthrow were
now past. It was adapted to political circumstances
characterised by a dominant capital city and an inadequate
communications system which made it impossible to concentrate
large masses of troops quickly from the countryside; and to a
level of technique in street-planning and military equipment
which gave considerable chances to street-fighting. It was then
that the foundations of a new strategy of the revolutionary
class were laid, which Engels eventually counterposed so sharply
to the old revolutionary strategy in his introduction to The
Class Struggles in France, and which can very well be
designated a strategy of attrition. This strategy has hitherto
won us the most shining successes, endowed the proletariat from
year to year with greater strength, and put it ever more at the
centre of European politics.’16
The nub of this strategy of attrition were
successive electoral campaigns, which Kautsky hopefully asserted
might give the SPD a numerical majority in the Reichstag next
year. Denying that aggressive mass strikes had any relevance in
the present conjuncture in Germany, Kautsky went on to advance
the idea of a geopolitical separation between Eastern and
Western Europe. In Tsarist Russia, Kautsky wrote, there was no
universal suffrage, no legal rights of assembly, no freedom of
the press. In 1905, the government was isolated at home, the
army defeated abroad, and the peasantry in revolt across the
vast and uncoordinated imperial territory. In these
circumstances, a strategy of overthrow was still possible. For
the Russian proletariat, which lacked elementary political or
economic rights, could launch an ‘amorphous and primitive’
revolutionary general strike, directed indifferently against
government and employers.17 The gathering storm of
mass strikes in Russia then spontaneously escalated to a
decisive contest with the state. In the event, the ‘policy of
violence’ pursued by the Russian working class encountered
ultimate defeat. But its strategy of overthrow was the natural
product of Russian society’s historical backwardness.
‘The conditions for a strike in Western Europe and
especially in Germany’, Kautsky went on, ‘are, however, very
different from those in pre-revolutionary and revolutionary
Russia.’18 In Western Europe, the workers were more
numerous and better organised, and they had long possessed civic
liberties. They were also confronted with a stronger class
enemy, equipped—above all in Germany—with a disciplined army and
bureaucracy. The Prussian state machine, in fact, was now the
most powerful in Europe. The working class was also more
isolated from other classes than in Russia. Hence tumultuous
mass strikes such as occurred during 1905 in Russia were
inappropriate in the West. ‘Demonstrations of this sort have
never yet occurred in Western Europe. Nor is it probable that
they will do so—not in spite, but because of half a century of
the socialist movement, social-democratic organisation and
political freedom.’19 In these circumstances, to
unleash mass strikes to secure the reform of the Prussian
franchise, as Luxemburg demanded, would merely compromise the
chances of the SPD at the next Reichstag elections. Formally,
Kautsky did not deny that in ‘the final battle’ of the class
struggle, a transition to a strategy of overthrow would be
necessary in the West too. But the weapon of the mass strike
should be reserved solely for this decisive engagement, when
victory or defeat would be absolute. For the moment,
‘preliminary skirmishes should not be fought with heavy
artillery’.20 The only correct path in the West was a
strategy of attrition, recalling that of Fabius Cunctator in
Ancient Rome.21
Luxemburg, whom Gramsci reproached for her
‘mysticism’ in his central text on East and West,22 grasped
the logic of Kautsky’s contrast between the two zones
immediately. The polemic between them on just this issue was the
occasion for her political break with Kautsky, four years in
advance of Lenin, who only understood it when war arrived in
1914. Luxemburg denounced the ‘whole theory of the two
strategies’ and its ‘crude contrast between revolutionary Russia
and parliamentary Western Europe’,23 as a
rationalisation of Kautsky’s refusal of mass strikes and his
capitulation to electoralism. She rejected Kautsky’s description
of the Russian Revolution of 1905: ‘The picture of a chaotic,
“amorphous and primitive” strike of the Russian workers … is a
flowering fantasy.’24 It was not political
backwardness but advance that distinguished the Russian
proletariat within the European working class. ‘The Russian
strikes and mass strikes, which gave form to so audacious a
creation as the famous Petersburg Soviet of Workers’ Delegates
for the unitary leadership of the whole movement in the enormous
Empire, were so little “amorphous and primitive” that in daring,
strength, solidarity, persistence, material achievements,
progressive goals and organisational successes, they can calmly
be set by the side of any “West European” trade-union movement.’25
Luxemburg dismissed Kautsky’s circumspect assessment
of the Prussian State, retorting that he had confused its police
crudity and brutality with political strength, for the purposes
of justifying timidity towards it. Kautsky’s avowed retention of
the use of a mass strike for the single apocalyptic contingency
of a ‘final battle’ in the distant future was a token clause,
designed to absolve the SPD from any commitment to serious
struggles in the concrete present, allowing it to settle for the
most mundane opportunism. Luxemburg’s political instinct led her
to isolate the ultimate drift of Kautsky’s arguments unerringly:
‘In practice, Comrade Kautsky directs us insistently towards the
coming Reichstag elections. These are the basic pillars of his
strategy of attrition. It is from the Reichstag elections that
salvation is to be expected. They will surely bring us an
overwhelming victory, they will create a wholly new situation,
they will immediately “put in our pocket the key to this
tremendous historical situation”. In a word, there are so many
violins in the heaven of the next Reichstag elections that we
would be criminally light-minded to think of any mass strike
when we have before us such a certain victory, put “in our
pocket” by the voting slip.’26 Luxemburg’s own
position in these debates was not without its flaws. She made no
adequate reply to Kautsky’s characterisation of the Russian
state, as opposed to the Russian working class, evading the
genuine problem of its structural difference from the Western
states of the time, which Kautsky had not been wrong to
emphasise. Nor did she possess, here or elsewhere, any etched
theory of the conquest of power by the proletariat—her
conception of mass strikes as continuous exercises in working
class autonomy and combativity blurring the inevitably
discontinuous rupture of a revolutionary rising against the
capitalist state itself, necessarily transcending the level of a
strike.27However, these limitations were secondary
when compared with the acuity of her insight into the dynamics
of Kautsky’s theory. Her prescience about its evolution is all
the more impressive when it is compared with Lenin’s
complaisance towards Kautsky.
For the debate within German social democracy had a
revealing sequel within Russian social democracy. A few weeks
later, Martov wrote an article in Die Neue Zeiton ‘The
Prussian Debate and Russian Experience’.28 Warmly
approving Kautsky’s overall theses, Martov argued that Russia
was actually in no way exempt from their lessons. Luxemburg
should not be allowed to utilise the Russian Revolution of 1905
as her ‘trump card’ against official SPD policy in Germany, nor
her account of it be conceded by Western socialists, in the name
of the privilegium odiosum of Russian exceptionalism.
Russian experience was now similar in every way to European
experience as a whole. Where it had diverged in 1905, it had
ended in disaster. The blending of economic with political
strikes, vaunted by Luxemburg, was a weakness rather than a
strength of the Russian proletariat. The Moscow uprising was the
calamitous result of an ‘artificial’ propulsion of the movement
towards a ‘decisive clash’ with the state. For Kautsky’s
sagacity was then unknown in Russia: ‘The idea of a “strategy of
attrition” occurred to no-one.’ Now, however, after the failure
of the extremism of 1905, it was the responsibility of the
Russian labour movement to adopt it. ‘The proletariat must
strive, not merely to struggle, but to win.’29
Martov’s prompt utilisation of Kautsky’s theses to
justify Menshevik policies in Russia duly provoked a reply from
the Polish Bolshevik Marchlewski in Die Neue Zeit.
Marchlewski’s response appears to have pre-empted Lenin’s own
reply—the latter desisting from a draft after Kautsky had
accepted a prior article on the same subject from the former.
Lenin, however, wrote to Marchlewski with suggestions for
inclusion in his answer to Martov, most of which were integrated
into the published text. The two documents are of the greatest
interest. For the burden of Marchlewski’s argument was that the
Bolsheviks in Russia had—contrary to Martov’s distortions—never
deviated from the logic of Kautsky’s precepts. On the contrary,
Marchlewski wrote, ‘Lenin’s recommendations were—if you like—the
same as Kautsky’s: due application of a “strategy of overthrow”
and of a “strategy of attrition” at the appropriate times for
them.’30 Now, in the long Tsarist reaction after the
revolution of 1905, it was the time for a strategy of attrition.
Russian social democracy must at present ‘learn to speak
German’.
Lenin himself meanwhile, in his letter to
Marchlewski, endorsed the validity of Kautsky’s claims of final
intransigence in his polemic with Luxemburg—indeed emphatically
reiterated them, despite the alacrity of Martov’s appropriation
of Kautsky’s arguments for a vindication of Menshevism in
Russia. ‘Rosa Luxemburg argued with Kautsky as to whether in
Germany the moment had arrived for Niederwerfungsstrategie,
and Kautsky plainly and bluntly stated that he considered this
moment was unavoidable and imminent but had not yet arrived …
All the Mensheviks seized on Rosa Luxemburg’s dispute with
Kautsky in order to declare Kautsky a “Menshevik”. Martov is
trying his hardest, by means of petty and miserable diplomacy,
to deepen the gulf between Rosa Luxemburg and Karl Kautsky.
These wretched devices cannot succeed. Revolutionary
social-democrats may argue about the timing of Niederwerfungsstrategie in
Germany, but not about its appropriateness in Russia in 1905.’31
The contrast with Luxemburg is striking. For
Luxemburg perceived at once that the real effect of Kautsky’s
arguments was a sophisticated apology for reformism. Her
vigorous denunciations of them received their vindication by the
end of the polemic between the two. For Luxemburg’s
characterisation of Kautsky’s theory as what she called Nichtsalsparlimentarismus—nothing
but parliamentarism—was finally confirmed in so many words by
Kautsky himself in one of his closing rejoinders, in a
formulation which sums up his position in a classic expression
of what can be called the social-democratic ‘defence clause’:
‘The more democratic the constitution of a country, the less
there exist conditions for a mass strike, the less necessary for
the masses does such a strike become, and therefore the less
often it happens. Where the proletariat possesses sufficient
electoral rights, a mass strike is only to be expected as a
defensive measure—as a means to protect voting rights or a
parliament with strong social-democratic representation, against
a government that refuses to obey the will of the people’s
representatives.’32
Gramsci, cut off from the outside world in prison
during the thirties, was unaware of these precedents while he
struggled to forge concepts to resist the renewal of adventurism
within the Comintern. It was in this context that he was able to
produce a notion formally analogous to that of Kautsky (strategy
of attrition/war of position), without seeing its dangers.
Gramsci’s ‘war of position’ was intended, as we have seen, as a
reply to Thalheimer’s and Lukács’s ‘war of manoeuvre’—in the
spirit, he believed, of the Comintern Congress that had
condemned them. The errors of the theory of the Teilaktion have
already been discussed. Did Gramsci’s formula, however,
completely correct them? It will be noticed that what he did was
in effect to invert their way of posing the problem.
Revolutionary strategy in Gramsci’s account becomes a long,
immobile trench war between two camps in fixed positions, in
which each tries to undermine the other culturally and
politically. ‘The siege is a reciprocal one’, Gramsci wrote,
‘concentrated, difficult, demanding exceptional qualities of
patience and invention.’33 There is no doubt that the
danger of adventurism disappears in this perspective, with its
overwhelming emphasis on the ideological allegiance of the
masses as the central object of struggle, to be gained only by
pursuit of a united front within the working class. But what
happens to the phase of insurrection itself—the storming and
destruction of the state machine that for Marx or Lenin were
inseparable from the proletarian revolution? Gramsci never
relinquished the basic tenets of classical Marxism on the
ultimate need for a violent seizure of state power, but his
strategic formula for the West failed to integrate them. The
mere counterposition of ‘war of position’ to ‘war of manoeuvre’
in any Marxist strategy in the end becomes an opposition between
reformism and adventurism.
An objection must immediately occur to such a
judgement. Why should Gramsci not have intended the strategy of
‘war of position’ to be a preparation for a concluding ‘war of
manoeuvre’ against the class enemy? In other words, did he not
in fact advocate a thesis that Lenin had wrongly ascribed to
Kautsky—the necessity of ‘a transition from the “strategy of
attrition” to the “strategy of overthrow” ’, a transition which
was ‘inevitable’ in the period of a political crisis when ‘the
revolution reaches its highest intensity’?34 In this
schema, Gramsci’s war of position would correspond to the phase
in which a revolutionary party seeks to win the masses
ideologically (consensually) to the cause of socialism, prior to
the phase in which it will lead them politically into a final
(coercive) revolt against the bourgeois State. ‘Hegemony’ would
then indeed be exercised within civil society, in the formation
of a class bloc of the exploited, while ‘dictatorship’ would be
asserted over against the exploiters, in the forcible
destruction of the state apparatus that secured their rule.
Such an interpretation would conform to the
classical principles of historical materialism. Yet in all the
2,000 pages of the Prison Notebooks, there is only one,
glancing sentence that appears to be in concordance with it.
Even that is oblique and ambiguous. At the very end of the long
passage comparing East and West which we have cited so often,
Gramsci penned a short afterthought—gratuitously suppressed by
his editors after the war. ‘One attempt to start a revision of
the current tactical methods was perhaps that outlined by
Trotsky at the Fourth World Congress, when he made a comparison
between the Eastern and Western fronts. The former had fallen at
once, but unprecedented struggles had then ensued; in the case
of the latter, the struggles would occur beforehand. The
question, therefore, was whether civil society resists before or
after the attempt to seize power; where the latter occurs, and
so on. However, the question was outlined only in a brilliant,
literary form, without directives of a practical character.’35
In this passage alone can be found a fleeting
instance of the correct theoretical and temporal order in which
Gramsci’s concepts should have been deployed, to yield a
revolutionary political strategy for advanced capitalism. For in
the West, the resistance of ‘civil society’ would precisely have
to be overcome before that of the state, by the work of the
United Front—yet victory within this arena would then have to be
succeeded by what Gramsci here directly calls an armed ‘assault’
(assalto) on the state. Unfortunately, the insight
contained in this allusion to another thinker was a passing one.
The weight of Gramsci’s own imagery—indeed cast in a ‘brilliant,
literary form’—in his central strategic texts goes in the
opposite direction. There it is the state which is merely an
‘outer ditch’, and civil society which is the ‘powerful system
of fortresses and earthworks’ that lies ‘behind’ it. In other
words, it is the civil society of capitalism—repeatedly
described as the domain of consent—that becomes the ultimate
barrier to the victory of the socialist movement. The war of
position is then the struggle by the organised working class to
win hegemony over it—a hegemony which by tacit definition merges
into a political paramountcy over the social formation as a
whole. ‘In politics, war of position is hegemony’, Gramsci
wrote, while ‘hegemony is rule by permanently organised
consent’.36
The theoretical slippage noted earlier thus recurs
again in Gramsci’s strategic thought, with yet more serious
consequences. For in a direct reversal of Lenin’s order of
battle, Gramsci expressly relegated ‘war of movement’ to a
merely preliminary or subsidiary role in the West, and promoted
‘war of position’ to the concluding and decisive role in the
struggle between labour and capital. In so doing, he was finally
trapped by the logic of his own concepts. The fatal passage
reads: ‘The war of position demands enormous sacrifices by
infinite masses of people. So an unprecedented concentration of
hegemony is necessary, and hence a more “interventionist”
government, which will take the offensive more directly against
oppositionists and organise permanently the “impossibility” of
internal disintegration—with controls of every kind, political,
administrative and other, reinforcement of the hegemonic
“positions” of the dominant group, and so on. All this indicates
that we have entered a culminating phase in the
political-historical situation, since in politics the “war of
position”, once won, is decisive definitively. In politics, in
other words, the war of manoeuvre subsists so long as it is a
question of winning positions that are not decisive.’37
The errors of this text have their suspect symptom:
the disquieting claims for the necessity of a more authoritarian
command within the ranks of the working class, capable of
suppressing all dissent. The association of the strategy of a
war of position with a centralised uniformity of political
expression, in homage to the worst side of the Comintern, is not
a reassuring one. In fact, the socialist revolution will only
triumph in the West by a maximum expansion—not constriction—of
proletarian democracy: for its experience alone, in parties or
councils, can enable the working class to learn the real limits
of bourgeois democracy, and equip it historically to surpass
them. For a Marxist strategy within advanced capitalism to
settle on a war of position and an ethos of command to achieve
the final emancipation of labour is to ensure its own defeat.
When the hour of reckoning in the class struggle arrives,
proletarian liberty and insurgency go together. It is their
combination, and no other, that can constitute a true social war
of movement capable of overthrowing capital in its strongest
bastions.
The political solution for the future of the Western
working class that Gramsci sought in prison, in the end eluded
him. The perspective of a war of position was a deadlock. In the
final analysis, the function of this idea in Gramsci’s thought
seems to have been that of a kind of moral metaphor: it
represented a sense of stoical adjustment to the loss of any
immediate hope of victory in the West. In one of those
coincidences that are a signature of the time, the Marxist
thinker in Western Europe whose fate was closest to that of
Gramsci in the thirties reproduced the same idea in his very
different work. Walter Benjamin, fellow victim of fascism,
expressed his political pessimism in the motto of a ‘tactic of
attrition’ (Ermattungstaktik)—for which his friend Brecht
commemorated him, unaware of any anterior history, on his death.38 The
poetic register of Benjamin’s notion tells us something about
the scientific status of Gramsci’s formula. The debt that every
contemporary Marxist owes to Gramsci can only be properly
acquitted if his writings are taken with the seriousness of real
criticism. In the labyrinth of the notebooks, Gramsci lost his
way. Against his own intention, formal conclusions can be drawn
from his work that lead away from revolutionary socialism.
Is it necessary to add that Gramsci was himself
proof against any sort of reformism? The parliamentarist
conclusions of Kautsky’s strategic theory were absolutely
foreign to him: his work is strewn elsewhere with assertions of
the imperative need for a revolutionary overthrow of the
capitalist state. We do not even have to look back at his
countless statements before prison and censorship. In the
document that can be regarded as Gramsci’s effective political
testament, his final direct counsel to the militants of the
Italian working class recorded by Athos Lisa, in which he
insisted in defiance of Third Period doctrines on the necessity
for popular intermediary objectives in the struggle against
fascism—above all, a constituent assembly—he also left no doubt
about his commitment to ultimate objectives, as Marx and Lenin
would have thought of them: ‘The violent conquest of power
necessitates the creation by the party of the working class of
an organisation of a military type, pervasively implanted in
every branch of the bourgeois State apparatus, and capable of
wounding and inflicting heavy blows on it at the decisive moment
of struggle.’39
Gramsci not merely asserted the need for proletarian
revolution in classical terms; many have done that verbally
since. He fought and suffered a long agony for it. Not merely
his work, but his life is incomprehensible without this
vocation. Gramsci himself was only too well aware of the
conditions of his struggle against illness, isolation and death.
The central passages in his notebooks on the distinction between
East and West are all cast in the form of an extended military
analogy: ‘artillery’, ‘trenches’, ‘commanders’, ‘manoeuvre’,
‘position’. The same man laconically warns us against any easy
reading of his own vocabulary. ‘In saying all this, the general
criterion should be remembered that comparisons between military
art and politics should always be taken with a pinch of salt—in
other words as aids to thought or terms in a reductio ad
absurdum.’40
The conditions of Gramsci’s composition in prison
produced a non-unitary, fragmentary theory, which inherently
allowed discrepancies and incoherences in it. Nothing reveals
this more clearly than the references to Trotsky in the central
texts discussed in this study. For in them, the concept of
‘Permanent Revolution’ is repeatedly the formal object of
Gramsci’s criticism, as the alleged expression of a ‘war of
manoeuvre’. Yet it was Trotsky who led the attack with Lenin on
the generalised theory of the ‘revolutionary offensive’ at the
Third Congress of the Comintern. It was Trotsky, again with
Lenin, who was the main architect of the United Front which
Gramsci equated with his ‘war of position’. Finally, it was
Trotsky, not Lenin, who wrote the document that was the
classical theorisation of the United Front in the twenties.41 Gramsci’s
confusion was here virtually total. The political proof of it
was to be very concrete. For during the height of the Third
Period in 1932, Gramsci in the prison of Turi di Bari and
Trotsky on the island of Prinkipo developed effectively
identical positions on the political situation in Italy, in
diametric contrast to the official line of the PCI and of the
Comintern. Prisoner and exile alike called for a United Front of
working class resistance to fascism including the
social-democratic parties, and a transitional perspective
including the possibility of a restoration of bourgeois
democracy in Italy after the fall of fascism.42 Neither,
of course, was aware of the other, in this convergence in the
political night of the time.
There is a further irony in Gramsci’s confusion,
beyond even this. For in point of fact, it was above all Trotsky
who provided the working class movement, East or West, with a
scientific critique of both the ideas of ‘war of manoeuvre’ and
‘war of position’, in the field where they really
obtained—military strategy proper. For the political doctrines
that emerged within the revolutionary movement of Central Europe
in 1920–21 had their military equivalent in Russia. There,
Frunze and Tukhachevsky played the role of Lukács and
Thalheimer. In the great military debates in the USSR after the
Civil War, Frunze, Tukhachevsky, Gusev and others had argued
that the essence of revolutionary warfare was permanent attack,
or war of manoeuvre. Tukhachevsky declared: ‘Strategic reserves,
the utility of which was always doubtful, we need not at all in
our war. Now there is only one question: how to use numbers to
gain the maximum force of the blow. There is one answer: release
all troops in the attack, not holding in reserve a single
bayonet.’43 Frunze claimed that the lessons of the
Civil War demonstrated that the primacy of the offensive for a
revolutionary strategy coincided with the social nature of the
proletariat itself: ‘The tactics of the Red Army were and will
be inspired with activity in the spirit of bold and
energetically conducted offensive operations. This proceeds from
the class nature of the workers’ and peasants’ army and at the
same time coincides with the exigencies of military art.’44 War
of position, characteristic of the First World War and of the
bourgeoisie, was henceforward an anachronism. ‘Manoeuvre is the
sole means of securing victory’, wrote Tukhachevsky.45
Trotsky, as we have seen, fought against the ‘theory
of the offensive’ as a strategy within the Comintern. He now
conducted a companion battle against it as a military doctrine
within the Red Army. Replying to Frunze and others, Trotsky made
the comparison himself: ‘Unfortunately, there are not a few
simpletons of the offensive among our new fashioned doctrinaires
who, under the banner of a military theory, are seeking to
introduce into our military circulation the same unilateral
“leftist” tendencies which at the Third World Congress of the
Comintern attained their fruition in the guise of the theory of
the offensive: inasmuch (!) as we are living in a revolutionary
epoch, therefore(!) the Communist Party must implement the
policy of the offensive. To translate “leftism” into the
language of military doctrine is to multiply this error many
times over.’46
Combating these conceptions, Trotsky exposed the
fallacy of generalizing from the experience of the Civil War, in
which both sides (not just the Red Army) had primarily used
manoeuvre, because of the backwardness of the social
organisation and military technique of the country. ‘Let me
point out that we are not the inventors of the manoeuvrist
principle. Our enemies also made extensive use of it, owing to
the fact that relatively small numbers of troops were deployed
over enormous distances and because of wretched means of
communication.’47 But above all Trotsky repeatedly
criticised any strategic theory that fetishised either manoeuvre
or position into an immutable or absolute principle. All wars
would combine position and manoeuvre, and any strategy that
unilaterally excluded one or the other was suicidal. ‘It is
possible to state with certainty that even in our
super-manoeuvrist strategy during the Civil War the element of
positionalism did exist and in certain instances played an
important role.’48 Therefore, Trotsky concluded:
‘Defense and offense enter as variable moments into combat …
Without the offensive, victory cannot be gained. But victory is
gained by him who attacks when it is necessary to attack and not
by him who attacks first.’49In other words, position
and manoeuvre had a necessarily complementary relationship in
any military strategy. To dismiss either one or the other was to
invite defeat and capitulation.
Having disposed of false analogies or extrapolations
whether in the Red Army or in the Comintern, Trotsky then went
on to make the prediction that in a genuinely military conflict
between classes—in other words an actual, not a metaphorical,
civil war—there would in all probability be a greater
positionalism in the West than there had been in the East. All
internal wars were naturally more manoeuvrist, because of the
scission they effected within state and nation, compared with
external wars between nations. In this respect, ‘manoeuvrability
is not peculiar to a revolutionary army but to civil war as
such’.50 However, the greater historical complexity
of economic and social structures in the advanced West would
render future civil wars there more positional in character than
in Russia. ‘In the highly developed countries with their huge
living centres, with their White Guard cadres prepared in
advance, civil war may assume—and in many cases undoubtedly will
assume—a far less mobile, a far more compact character, that is,
one approximating to positional war.’51 In the final,
dwindling moments of Gramsci’s life, Europe was visited by just
such a conflict. The Spanish Civil War was to vindicate
Trotsky’s judgement arrestingly. Fought on the Manzanares and
the Ebro, the battle for the Republic proved a long positional
ordeal—lost in the end because the working class could never
regain the initiative of manoeuvre essential to victory. If
Trotsky’s analysis was to be confirmed in Spain, it was because
of its pertinence to its object. It was a technical, not a
metaphorical, theory of war.
Trotsky’s military accuracy, the product of his
experience in the Russian Civil War, did not necessarily confer
an equivalent privilege on his political strategy. His knowledge
of Germany, England and France was in point of fact greater than
that of Gramsci. His writings on the three major social
formations of Western Europe in the inter-war period are
commensurately superior to those in the Prison Notebooks.
They contain indeed the only developed theory of a modern
capitalist state in classical Marxism, in his texts on Nazi
Germany. Yet while Trotsky’s historical command of the specific
sociopolitical structures of capitalism in the central countries
of Western Europe had no equal in his own time, he never posed
the problem of a differential strategy for making the socialist
revolution in them, unscheduled by that in Russia, with the same
anxiety or lucidity as Gramsci. In this essential respect, his
questions were less troubled.
5
IMPLICATIONS
Gramsci’s answers to his problems did not, as we
have seen, resolve them. The lessons of the debate between
Kautsky and Luxemburg, the contrast between Lukács and Gramsci,
can however today at least yield two simple and concrete
propositions. To formulate proletarian strategy in metropolitan
capitalism essentially as a war of manoeuvre is to forget the
unity and efficacy of the bourgeois state and to pit the working
class against it in a series of lethal adventures. To formulate
proletarian strategy as essentially a war of position is to
forget the necessarily sudden and volcanic character of
revolutionary situations, which by the nature of these social
formations can never be stabilised for long and therefore need
speed and mobility of attack if the opportunity to conquer power
is not to be missed. Insurrection, Marx and Engels always
emphasised, depends on the art of audacity.
In Gramsci’s case, the inadequacies of the formula
of a ‘war of position’ had a clear relationship to the
ambiguities of his analysis of bourgeois class power. Gramsci
equated ‘war of position’ with ‘civil hegemony’, it will be
remembered. Thus just as his use of hegemony often tended to
imply that the structure of capitalist power in the West
essentially rested on culture and consent, so the idea of a war
of position tended to imply that the revolutionary work of a
Marxist party was essentially that of ideological conversion of
the working class—hence its identification with the United
Front, whose aim was to win a majority of the Western
proletariat to the Third International. In both cases, the role
of coercion—repression by the bourgeois state, insurrection by
the working class—tends to drop out. The weakness of Gramsci’s
strategy is symmetrical with that of his sociology.
What is the contemporary relevance of these past
debates over Marxist strategy? Any real discussion of the
problems of the present would involve many questions to which
there has been no allusion here. The limits of a philological
survey have dictated these inevitable restrictions. Such central
issues as the interconnexion of economic and political struggles
in the labour movement, the alliances of the working class in
largely post-peasant societies, the contemporary nature of
capitalist crises, the possible catalysts and forms of dual
power, the development of more advanced institutions of
proletarian democracy—wider and freer than any past
precedents—are all omitted here. Yet to deliberate in isolation
from them on the structures of the bourgeois state and the
strategies necessary for the working class to overthrow it, can
lead to an irresponsible abstraction—unless these necessary
other elements of any Marxist theory of the socialist revolution
in the West are always recollected. If we accept this
limitation, what can be concluded from the heritage
reconstructed in this essay? There is space, and occasion, here
for only two comments, confined to the subjects of its debate.
The logic of Marxist theory indicates that it is in
the nature of the bourgeois state that, in any final contest,
the armed apparatus of repression will displace the ideological
apparatuses of parliamentary representation, to re-occupy the
dominant position in the structure of capitalist class power.
This coercive state machine is the ultimate barrier to a
workers’ revolution, and can only be broken by pre-emptive
counter-coercion. In the nineteenth century, barricades provided
the traditional symbol of the latter. Yet Lenin long ago pointed
out that these fortifications often had a moral rather than
military function: their purpose was classically as much a
fraternisation with soldiers as a weapon against them. For in
any revolution, the task of a proletarian vanguard, in Lenin’s
words, is not merely to fight against the troops but for the
troops. This does not mean, he emphasised, mere verbal
persuasion to join the camp of the proletariat, but a ‘physical
struggle’ by the masses to win them over to the side of the
revolution.1
An insurrection can only succeed if the repressive
apparatus of the state itself divides or disintegrates—as it did
in Russia, China or Cuba. The consensual ‘convention’ that holds
the forces of coercion together must, in other words, be
breached. The armies of Western Europe, North America and Japan
today are composed of conscripts or recruits from the exploited
classes, who possess a potential capacity to paralyse
counter-revolutionary mobilisation in a general crisis. A key
objective of political struggle is thus always to act on the
enlisted men with class audacity and resolve, to break the unity
of the repressive apparatus of the state. In other words, a
proletarian rising is always a political operation, whose
fundamental aim is not to inflict casualties on the enemy, but
to rally all the exploited masses together, whether in overalls
or in uniform, women as well as men, for the creation of a new
popular power. Yet it is also, however, necessarily a military
operation. For no matter how successful the working class is in
dividing the coercive apparatus of the state (army or police),
detaching major segments from it, and winning them over to the
cause of the revolution, there still always remains an
irreducible core of counter-revolutionary forces, specially
trained and hardened in their repressive functions, who cannot
be converted; who can only be defeated. The Petrograd Garrison
went over to the Military Revolutionary Committee: the Junkers
and the Cossacks in the Winter Palace still resisted. The
infantry and artillery may have rallied to the cause of
socialism in Portugal: the commandos and air force remained
intact to suppress it.
Where the domestic institutions of repression
disintegrate too suddenly or drastically, it is the external
intervention of stronger military apparatuses from abroad,
controlled by more powerful bourgeois states, that will be
deployed—the ‘foreign currency’ of coercion towards which local
capital moves in flight when its own reserves sink too low. The
examples, from Russia to Spain, from Cuba to Vietnam, are common
knowledge. The duality—internal or international—of the armed
apparatus of the enemy is an unvarying element of every
revolution. Trotsky captured it with accuracy: ‘The workers must
in advance take all measures to draw the soldiers to the side of
the people by means of preliminary agitation; but at the same
time they must foresee that the government will always be left
with a sufficient number of dependable or semi-dependable
soldiers for them to call out for the purposes of quelling an
insurrection; and consequently in the final resort the question
has to be decided by an armed conflict.’2 The
determination of the capitalist state in the final instance by
coercion thus holds true of the coercive apparatus itself.
Ideological and political struggle can undermine a bourgeois
military machine in a revolutionary crisis, by a consensual
conquest of the men enlisted in it. But the hard core of
professional counter-revolutionary units—marines, paratroops,
riot police or paramilitary gendarmerie—can only be swept away
by the coercive attack of the masses. From beginning to end, the
laws of the capitalist state are reflected and refused in the
rules of a socialist revolution.
Such a revolution will only occur in the West when
the masses have made the experience of a proletarian democracy
that is tangibly superior to bourgeois democracy. The sole way
for the victory of socialism to be secured in these societies is
for it to represent incontestably more, not less, freedom for
the vast majority of the population. It is the untapped store of
popular energies any inception of a real workers’ democracy
would release that will provide the explosive force capable of
ending the rule of capital. For the exhibition of a new,
unprivileged liberty must start before the old order is
structurally cancelled by the conquest of the state. The name of
this necessary overlap is dual power. The ways and means of its
emergence—with or without the presence of a workers’ government
in office—constitute the critical intermediate problem of any
socialist revolution. For the moment, however, the working class
movement in most of the countries of the West is some distance
away from this threshold. It is no doubt the case that the
majority of the exploited population in every major capitalist
social formation today remains subject in one way or another to
reformist or capitalist ideology. It is here that the most
durable political theme of Gramsci’s Notebooks acquires
its sense. For the task that the United Front was designed to
acquit is still unsolved fifty years later. The masses in North
America, Western Europe and Japan have yet to be won over to
revolutionary socialism. Therefore, the central problematic of
the United Front—the final strategic advice of Lenin to the
Western working class movement before his death, the first
concern of Gramsci in prison—retains all its validity today. It
has never been historically surpassed. The imperative need
remains to win the working class before there can be any talk of
winning power. The means of achieving this conquest—not of the
institutions of the state, but of the convictions of workers,
although in the end there will be no separation of the two—are
the prime agenda of any real socialist strategy today.
The international disputes which united and divided
Luxemburg, Lenin, Lukács, Gramsci, Bordiga or Trotsky on these
issues represent the last great strategic debate in the European
workers’ movement. Since then, there has been little significant
theoretical development of the political problems of
revolutionary strategy in metropolitan capitalism that has had
any direct contact with the masses. The structural divorce
between original Marxist theory and the main organisations of
the working class in Europe has yet to be historically resolved.
The May–June revolt in France, the upheaval in Portugal, the
approaching denouement in Spain, presage the end of this long
divorce, but have not accomplished it. The classical debates,
therefore, still remain in many respects the most advanced limit
of reference we possess today. It is thus not mere archaism to
recall the strategic confrontations which occurred four or five
decades ago. To reappropriate them, on the contrary, is a step
towards a Marxist discussion that has the—necessarily
modest—hope of assuming an ‘initial shape’ of correct theory
today. Régis Debray has spoken, in a famous paragraph, of the
constant difficulty of being contemporary with our present. In
Europe at least, we have yet to be sufficiently contemporary
with our past.
ANNEXE:
ATHOS LISA’S REPORT
Introductory Note
In the autumn of 1930, Gramsci gave a series of
talks in the courtyard of the jail at Turi near Bari where he
was held, in which he expressed his political ideas directly to
his fellow prisoners without having to resort to the prudent
ciphers and allusions of his notebooks, composed under the eye
of censors. That we have a record of what he said is due to one
of his listeners, who at the time strongly disagreed with him.
Athos Lisa, an almost exact contemporary—he was born in 1890,
Gramsci a few months later—was a railway worker from Pisa.
Originally a socialist, after escaping from the police to France
he joined the Communist Party in 1924, returning to Italy and
working in its underground until his arrest in late 1926.
Sentenced to nine years in prison, after spending two of these
in the harshest confinement on the islands of Santo Stefano and
Pianosa, he was transferred to Turi a few weeks after Gramsci
started giving his lectures, remaining there till the autumn of
1931, when he was invalided out to another prison in Lazio,
returning to Turi a year later. In October 1932 he was included
in an amnesty, and on his release made his way to Paris, where
the exiled leadership of the PCI was based.
There in February 1933 he wrote a report for it on
the imprisoned Gramsci’s political views, for which Togliatti
thanked him and told him never to speak of it to anyone. In
France he served in Red Aid, the Communist organisation for
support of political prisoners, and did relief work for victims
of the Spanish Civil War, before joining the Resistance in the
Alpes Maritimes during the Second World War. After Liberation he
helped the CGT produce a paper for Italian workers in France. At
the height of the Cold War, he was expelled from France in 1951,
returning to Pisa when he was in his early sixties. As a
disciplined militant, he never mentioned the existence of the
report to anyone, and had no idea what had happened to it.
A decade later, Togliatti died in Yalta. On 25
August 1964, a vast funeral procession followed his bier in
Rome. Within a few months, Athos Lisa’s report was published in
the PCI’s weekly Rinascita on 12 December 1964, thirty
years after it was written. Its author remained silent, dying
soon afterwards in April 1965. Some time after his death, his
widow found the manuscript of a memoir he had tucked away in the
pages of an encyclopaedia, of which he had never spoken even to
her. He must have completed it in the last months of his life,
since it included the text of his report of 1933, of which he
had possessed no copy since handing it over to Togliatti, and a
note explaining why he omitted the opening sentences reproduced
in Rinascita. Eventually, in 1973, the memoir was edited
and published by the last survivor of Communist leadership born
in the 1890s, the heterodox Umberto Terracini.1 The
text printed below is the fifth chapter of the book, containing
both Lisa’s report of Gramsci’s lectures in prison and his
description of what followed them in the conditions of each at
Turi di Bari.
Kept secret when it was written, revealed only after
the death of the leader who made sure it had remained so, the
Athos Lisa report has not ceased to be explosive to this day.
The reason why Togliatti concealed it in 1933 lay in what
Gramsci called his ‘punch in the eye’ to the official line of
the party: his call for a Constituent Assembly to rally all
anti-fascist forces in Italy, as a transitional objective in the
advance towards a socialist revolution for which the communist
party did not yet command sufficient support to aim
outright—this, at a time when the PCI leadership was propagating
the delusions of the Third Period of the Comintern that
revolution was around the corner and the only force against
fascism was itself. After 1935, the Comintern switched to the
strategy of a Popular Front, but since it did so without any
allusion to its previous sectarian line, let alone
self-criticism for it, Lisa’s report had still to be suppressed,
as damning evidence of past error and the fate that Togliatti
had dealt Gramsci’s rejection of it.
Within a decade of its release after Togliatti’s
death, however, the report became an embarrassment to the PCI,
no longer as a deviation to the ‘right’ of the party’s line, but
as all too awkward evidence of how far Gramsci’s politics were
to the ‘left’ of it. Now proclaiming a peaceful, parliamentary
road to a better future—ever more vaguely defined, references to
socialism giving way to talk simply of a more ‘advanced
democracy’, indistinguishable from traditional social-democratic
parlance, the party had no less reason to want to occlude the
report, since it made plain that Gramsci was fully committed to
a violent overthrow of the capitalist state, setting out the
kind of military organisation the party needed to create for
this purpose, and treating hegemony in the classic Leninist
acceptation of the term as the task of winning the peasantry and
petty bourgeoisie as allies for the working class in its battle
to sweep away the bourgeoisie. At the antipodes of the ‘historic
compromise’ the PCI was seeking with the DC, the leading party
of the Italian bourgeoisie, such conceptions were anathema to
its recent transmogrification. Athos Lisa’s report had now
either to be ignored, as if it had never existed, or subjected
to risible glosses, presenting it as—if read properly—a virtual
anticipation of the party’s current line, or finally as the work
of a dim, doubtfully reliable cadre whose primitive
understanding of Gramsci’s ideas was also in part a function of
Gramsci’s need to dumb these down for the low intellectual level
of his fellow prisoners.2
Ostensibly, in this cleansing of the past, the one
idea in the Athos Lisa report to survive lustration is what
originally made it too hot to handle in Paris. Gramsci had
called for a Constituent Assembly in 1933, and in 1946 a
Constituent Assembly there duly was, which wrote the Italian
Constitution that today’s descendant of the PCI, the Democratic
Party of Matteo Renzi, has sought—but failed—to whittle down as
too radical. Still, it might be asked, is not the larger fact
that Gramsci’s best political idea was vindicated by history, in
the creation of as post-war Italian democracy of which his party
was a key founder? The reality is more bitter. Gramsci, as he
explained to others in prison, not only saw a Constituent
Assembly as a way-station en route to a destination remote from
anything envisaged by the party after the war. He stipulated
that all who were heavily compromised by fascism should be
excluded from its voting rolls. So far from anything like this
occurring, no serious purge of any kind was made of fascist
officials in the Italian state apparatus after 1945, when
Togliatti was Minister of Justice, virtually every prefect, let
alone subordinate, who had served Mussolini remaining in place.
Among these officials was the very military judge, Enrico Macis,
who had sent Gramsci to his martyrdom in prison. Promoted for
his service to the regime in staging Gramsci’s trial, along with
that of many other Communists, Macis went on to military duties
in Mussolini’s conquest of Ethiopia and then the fascist seizure
of Slovenia, annexed to Italy during the war. There he presided
over deportations and repressions that earned him the highest
praise of the generals in command of the Italian occupation, and
a Slovene demand for his extradition as a war criminal after
1945. In post-war Italy, not a hair of his head was touched. He
was even called upon for help in organising an anti-fascist
exhibition in Milan, and lived out the rest of the days till
1973 in complete tranquillity.3 At no point did the
PCI lift a finger to expose him or bring him to justice. To read
Lisa’s description of what Gramsci endured at the hands of this
figure is a reminder of what his party preferred to forget.
MEMOIR
When the number of political prisoners at Turi di
Bari increased, our desire for some assessment of the situation
in Italy and the party’s line on it became more pressing, also
because the new arrivals in prison brought us contradictory news
of these. At first Gramsci didn’t seem eager to express himself,
not because he didn’t have clear ideas on the subject but
because of the objective difficulty of broaching such a complex
subject in front of an audience as large as ours within a
prison. To do so would have required many hours. Gramsci feared
that this could draw the attention of the prison authorities,
giving them an excuse for restrictive measures that would affect
everyone. However, after having devised certain preventive
measures to avoid alarming them, Gramsci finally decided to
address the subject that was so close to his heart. For about a
fortnight, during our time in the courtyard every morning,
Gramsci spoke of Italy’s political and economic situation, the
relationship of forces and the international conjuncture, with
such acuity and depth that he surprised even those who had heard
him speak before his arrest.
When Gramsci began his report on the Italian and
international situation he warned us that what he was about to
tell us would be a kind of ‘punch in the eye’, since he would
talk about the ‘Constituent Assembly’.4 At the time,
his abrupt formulation and schematic treatment of this subject,
in isolation from a series of questions that I felt could not be
ignored without turning an essentially political problem into an
academic argument, gave me the impression of a casual boutadethrown
out to animate our daily discussions. Later I realised that
Gramsci had planned his ‘punch in the eye’ quite deliberately,
tackling many political problems both before and after he
delivered it in the same spirit, with the same logic, to the
same purpose. In fact, he told us that he had thought long and
hard about the question of a Constituent Assembly, to which he
attached the greatest political importance, since in his view it
commanded the tactics the party should follow.
The opposition he expressed on this issue was
preceded by two talks on ‘intellectuals and the party’ and ‘the
military problem and the party’, whose basic ideas I will try to
report since they struck me as closely connected with his
conception of the Constituent Assembly, or at any rate allowed
me to see the general train of his thought. In the first,
Gramsci argued that intellectuals are absolutely necessary for
the proletariat, both in historical periods when it is a class
in-itself and in those when it is a class for-itself. Without
intellectuals the proletariat could neither come to power, nor
consolidate or develop its power after winning it. But who
should be considered intellectuals, and among these, on whom
should the party concentrate its work? The intellectuals of the
working class, Gramsci said, are the elements that make up the
vanguard of the proletariat: the party. In support of this idea
Gramsci drew an analogy between the party and certain branches
of bourgeois state organisation, taking its factories and armed
services as examples. In both of these he classified those who
exercise a function beyond mere execution of physical tasks as
intellectuals or semi-intellectuals. In factories, he considered
intellectuals all those—for example engineers or
managers—responsible for putting into practice plans laid down
in general form by the owner of the enterprise or its board. He
classed as semi-intellectuals those in charge of the technical
or administrative oversight of labour, for example
superintendents, foremen, team leaders, clerks at various
levels. In the army, he considered intellectuals all senior
officers to whom the general staff assign the concretisation of
tactical or strategic plans, and semi-intellectuals all
those—NCOs and junior officers—responsible for seeing that these
are executed correctly by the troops. In Gramsci’s view, the
organisation of the party, with its central committee above and
its peripheral organisations below, followed the same model.
Defining intellectuals in this way by particular
activities, Gramsci wanted to establish a sharp distinction
between different social categories, in order to separate the
kind of intellectual that could be of interest to the party from
bourgeois intellectuals. Thus, following Gramsci’s analysis, the
directors and chief executives of companies, generals, leaders
of philosophical schools etc. should be considered the purest
representatives of the bourgeoisie.
Discussing ‘the military problem and the party’,
Gramsci made it clear that the violent conquest of power
necessitates the creation by the party of an organisation of a
military type, pervasively implanted within every branch of the
bourgeois state apparatus, and capable of wounding and
inflicting heavy blows on it at the decisive moment of struggle.
The problem of military organisation had to be understood,
however, as part of the much wider work of the party, for this
particular activity presupposed tight interdependence with the
whole range of its practical actions and its ideological
development. The purely technical aspect of military
organisation was not to be considered in isolation. Decisive for
its capability and efficacy was its political direction. Those
in charge of it needed unusual qualities, which were in many
ways a function of the ideological level of the party. An
unconditional requirement of the proletarian revolution, Gramsci
said, is a shift in the relations of armed force in favour of
the working class. But by military relations of force should be
understood not just possession of weapons or combat units, but
the ability of the party to paralyse the nerve centres of the
bourgeois state apparatus. For example: a general strike can
shift the military relations of force in favour of the working
class. Accurate intelligence of the strength of the enemy was
also an indispensable condition of waging civil war. In an
overview of the Italian military, he listed regular troops and
specialised forces like the carabinieri, militia, state police
and retired officers. He attributed great importance to this
last category as a military and political force. Given Italy’s
geographical configuration, amongst the most important offensive
weapons of the enemy he noted armoured trains. Running along the
Adriatic or Ionian coast, these could immobilise and sow terror
among the population, wherever the party had not created a
military organisation capable in some measure of paralysing the
operation of these powerful instruments of bourgeois action.
I mentioned that Gramsci presented his view of the
issue of the ‘Constituent Assembly’ because he wanted to hear
our ideas about it. Like other comrades who heard his
exposition, I had the impression Gramsci attached a lot of
importance to our response to his talk. He never tired of
repeating that the party suffered from maximalism and that his
work of political education among us aimed at creating a core of
people capable of a healthier ideological contribution to it.
Too often in the party, he said, there is a fear of anything
that doesn’t belong to the old maximalist phrasebook. People
think the proletarian revolution is something that at a certain
point arrives ready-made. Every tactical move that doesn’t
conform to a dreamy subjectivism is considered a distortion of
the tactics and strategy of the revolution. So there is often
talk about revolution without any precise idea of what would be
needed to bring it about, of the means necessary to achieve it
as an end, or how to adapt these means to different historical
situations. There was a general tendency to elevate words over
political action, or to confuse the two. That’s why Gramsci
termed the issue of the Constituent Assembly a ‘punch in the
eye’.
His presentation of this theme focussed on two
conceptions: 1) the tactics of winning allies for the
proletariat; 2) the tactics of winning power. He developed these
roughly as follows. Italian reaction, in depriving the
proletariat of its party, class organisations, press, and any
legal opportunity for meetings and strikes, had stripped it of
the most indispensable means of struggle for a relatively rapid
achievement of its hegemony as a class. Italy was primarily an
agricultural country marked by a great disparity between North
and South in both its economic structures and social layers
within the labouring classes; the industrial development in the
South lagged behind that of the North even as capital became
more centralised; for historical reasons the peasantry continued
to be ideologically subordinate in some degree to
petty-bourgeois elements, who formed the best relay for the
agrarian bourgeoisie to keep down the peasantry. The task for
the Italian proletariat of winning over allied classes was
therefore extremely delicate and difficult. But without gaining
their support, the proletariat had no chance of building any
serious revolutionary movement. Given the particular historical
conditions that had cramped the political development of
peasants and petty bourgeois in Italy, and the currently limited
possibilities for the party greatly to alter their political and
organisational backwardness, it was not hard to grasp that the
party needed a line of action that, by unfolding in stages,
became comprehensible and accessible to these social layers.
In present conditions of popular life and struggle,
the peasant and especially the rural petty bourgeois were not
capable of identifying with the Communist Party, or its slogans
and ultimate aims. These social strata could come to a direct
struggle for power only by stages: that is, if the party led
them step by step to see the justice of its programme and the
falsity of that of other political parties, in whose demagogy
peasants and petty bourgeois still believed. Today it would be
easy enough to convince a Southern peasant that the King was
superfluous, but much harder that he could be replaced by a
worker, just as he doesn’t believe it would be possible for him
to replace his master. A petty bourgeois or junior officer in
the army, frustrated by precarious living conditions or lack of
promotion, will more easily believe his lot would improve in a
republican regime than a soviet system. The first step towards
which these social strata needed to be guided was to express
themselves on constitutional and institutional issues. Every
worker, even the most backward peasant of Basilicata or
Sardinia, now understood the uselessness of the monarchy.
On this terrain the party could join forces with
other parties fighting against fascism in Italy, but should not
tail them. The aim of the party was the violent conquest of
power and establishment of the dictatorship of the proletariat,
to be achieved by tactical adjustment to its historical
situation and the balance of class forces in successive phases
of the struggle. Assuming the party could navigate these, its
political ability would then depend on a passage beyond its
intermediate demands, as so many stages in unblocking the social
strata it had to win over for a shift in the balance of forces.
Yet even if the pressure of reaction in Italy slackened in the
immediate future, action by the party would still face great
difficulties. At best, it could count on no more than 6,000
active members. Divide that by the number of regions in Italy
and the limits to its efficacy leapt to the eye. In conditions
like these there could be no talk of conquering power without
passing through a period of transition, however relatively
limited its duration.
There were two scenarios for revolution in Italy,
one more likely than the other. Gramsci held it that the most
probable would involve a period of transition. The tactics of
the party should envisage this without fear of appearing not
very revolutionary. It should make the slogan of a Constituent
Assembly its own, not as an end in itself but as a means, before
any other anti-fascist party adopted it. The Assembly would
offer an institutional framework for its representatives to pose
the most urgent demands of the working class, to discredit every
scheme for peaceful reform, and to show the Italian working
class that the only viable solution for Italy lay in a
proletarian revolution. Here Gramsci liked to recall the
‘Association of Young Sardinia’ of Turin in 1919, when
well-judged and timely action by the Party had rallied the poor
against the rich, enrolling them in the Sardinian socialist
educational society within the chamber of trade unions. As a
direct consequence, soldiers from the Sassari Brigade of the
army had taken the side of Turin’s working class. This, he said,
was a bit like a small Constituent Assembly. He added that the
first article in the Bolshevik programme for government had
included the demand for a Constituent Assembly. To reach an
agreement with the antifascist parties from a position of
political independence and superior strength, the party must lay
claim to the same idea. In this way our tactics would lead us,
without worrying about labels, to achieve the aims the party had
set itself.
Following a disagreement with me, Gramsci—who had so
far not said at what point a Constituent Assembly could be
realised—added he thought that as economic conditions in Italy
worsened we would see sporadic but recurrent outbreaks of
popular unrest, and this ferment would be the sign that a
Constituent Assembly had become feasible in Italy. But the party
should start calling for one right away. Since he assumed the
objective conditions for a proletarian revolution had existed in
Europe for over fifty years, comrade Gramsci’s analysis set
aside any assessment of the interdependence of the Italian
economy with that of other capitalist states, the inherent
consequences of the deepening world economic crisis, the
radicalisation of the working class and disintegration in the
social support of certain pseudo-proletarian (social-democratic)
parties, or the political influence at large of the development
of the Soviet economy. We must, he said, be more political,
better able to act politically, less afraid of doing politics.
Pausing incidentally to consider the slogan of ‘workers’ and
peasants’ government’, he said that this was historically
superseded and should be replaced by a ‘republic of workers’ and
peasants’ soviets in Italy’. This argument was not developed by
Gramsci, but as far as I remember the implication was that the
slogan ‘workers’ and peasants’ government’ had been appropriated
by the pseudo-proletarian and democratic parties, suggesting a
shift in their social base. I could not say whether Gramsci
meant that this shift had pushed these parties to the left, or
simply to a more demagogic phraseology.
After Gramsci’s presentation, we were invited to
express our own opinions on the call for a Constituent Assembly.
Each, within the limits of their ability, said what they thought
and on the whole nearly everyone agreed with Gramsci’s
positions. Those in favour were comrades Tulli, Lai, Piacentini,
Ceresa, Spadoni, Lo Sardo and a few others whose names I don’t
exactly recall. Those against were Scucchia from Rome and
myself. Nevertheless, at Gramsci’s express wish, all those
present at the discussion were invited to reconsider the
question and come back to say what they thought a fortnight
later. This never happened because Gramsci, under the influence
of false information, thought that discussions among comrades
put in separate sections of the prison were becoming factional.
At a brief meeting Gramsci announced that he would
suspend ongoing conversations among comrades for six months
because political education was lacking. So the question of the
‘Constituent Assembly’ was born and died in Turi di Bari, while
it remained alive in the mind of comrade Gramsci—so much so that
in October 1932 he spoke of it to me with the same deep
conviction and enthusiasm he had shown in 1930.
The day after Gramsci’s presentation I asked him to
set out his view of fascism—what he thought were the historical
conditions that had produced it, what interests it represented
and where its social composition lay. I felt that our
perspectives on the Italian situation could not be objective
without a clear understanding of all this. Gramsci agreed to my
proposal and the next day outlined a retrospective history of
fascism that I will try to summarise as succinctly as I can, to
avoid distorting Gramsci’s ideas amid details.
Here is what he argued:
Fascism as we see it in Italy is a peculiar form of
bourgeois reaction which emerged out of specific historical
conditions of the bourgeoisie in general and our country in
particular. Italian fascism could not be accurately understood
without situating it in the history of the Italian people, and
the economic and political structures of Italy. If we want a
more grounded explanation of the particular features of the form
of reaction called fascism in Italy, we have to go back, at
least, to the historical matrices of successive stages in the
unification of the Italian state, to the nefarious influence of
the church, to the actions of democracy and social democracy.
The lack of any political unity of the Italian bourgeoisie,
rooted in the economic structure of our country, and conspicuous
during the period of struggles for Italian independence,
accounts in good part for the origin and development of fascism,
which acquired the function of uniting all bourgeois forces,
once the historical conditions were ripe for doing so.
Conversely, the absence of any true
bourgeois–democratic revolution in Italy, which left unsolved a
whole series of problems whose resolution would have given
greater cohesion to the Italian bourgeoisie, sharpened the class
struggle and accelerated the development of the proletariat. If
by participating in the First World War the Italian bourgeoisie
seemed to achieve a unity it had never before known, the
post-war period reopened all the contradictions that the war had
in part attenuated, reproducing in exacerbated form all the old
problems of Italian society. This was a historical moment
defined by what could be called a parallelism between the forces
ranged against each other. On one side the bourgeois forces
fought without any political unity to impose the costs of the
war on the working class, while on the other the working class
led by the Socialist Party fought for the conquest of power
without itself having achieved any class unity. But while the
Italian proletariat, misled by the Socialist Party, diluted its
revolutionary potential in tactics that did not lead to the
conquest of power, the bourgeoisie succeeded in regrouping its
forces to combat the working class.
The first phase of the fascist movement, which began
with violent squads paid by landowners in some agricultural
areas and particularly the Po Valley, was an expression of the
bourgeois struggle against workers in general and in particular
the struggle of the rural bourgeoisie against the association of
agricultural labourers. The tactics of the Italian bourgeoisie
followed two trajectories: one aimed against the trade unions
and the other against the Federterra. The arrow of its attack,
however, started in the countryside before turning on the
cities, reversing the traditional throttling of Italian rural
society by the towns. At first, the elements active in the
fascist organisations were recruited from the dregs of society.
In a second phase, after Giolitti’s government lent its support,
they came from the rural and urban petty bourgeoisie, which
believed that its turn had come to determine the future of
Italy. This moment coincided with a broadening of the social
bases of fascism, and a subsidence of the revolutionary impetus
that had found expression in the movement of factory
occupations. All further developments in the political struggle
in Italy reflected, through the prism of tumultuous and
contradictory actions of the Fascist Party, phases in the
conflict between the proletariat and the action–reaction of the
social classes deployed by the bourgeoisie against it. This
process moved more or less in parallel with a centralisation of
capital in Italy resulting in the dominance of finance
capitalism, to the interests of which the politics of fascism
became subordinate.
Thus at a certain moment fascism became the form of
organisation called upon to defend the interests of this sector
of the Italian bourgeoisie, while at the same time managing, to
a certain degree and by various means, to mitigate differences
among the interests of the class as a whole. This performance
was facilitated by the anti-democratic character of so many
Italian institutions, including a legal system that inhibited
any possibility of checking the overweening power of the
strongest economic groups, a parliament subject to the
discretionary powers of the king, a judiciary that was
non-elective, and so on.
Along with this centralisation of the forces of the
bourgeoisie had come, moving at a much slower pace, a
radicalisation of the working class—a process of which the
Communist Party and its ideology was in part an expression.
Although fascism had failed completely in its aim of resolving
the economic crisis, it did allow the Italian bourgeoisie to
overcome the deep political crisis of the post-war years without
too much turbulence, achieving a relative stabilisation of its
position. Of course this was at the expense of the working
class. Though so far contained, the Italian economic crisis
would certainly deepen, with consequences already visible in
worker and peasant unrest, and rising economic and political
discontent. The objective conditions for a conquest of power by
the proletariat were already all there. But these were not
enough. Wide layers of the masses—especially peasant—lacked the
political maturity of workers. The influence of
pseudo-proletarian socialist parties and cliques had not yet
been destroyed. The party faced the urgent problem of achieving
the hegemony of the proletariat, without which the conquest of
power would be impossible. It should be prepared for the
bourgeoisie to take extreme measures in its own defence, which
in Italy might go as far as conceding land to the peasantry. The
greatest problem remained the correlation of class forces.
Taking account of its specificities in our country, the party’s
action should aim at rapidly shifting the balance of power in
favour of the working class.
In summarising Gramsci’s ideas, I have relied on the
accuracy of my memory, setting aside any sectarian element and
trying not to invalidate them with my own views. I cannot
guarantee I have reported exactly everything Gramsci told us two
and a half years ago. Whoever reads and wants to discuss the
findings in this report should bear that in mind.5
I never heard Gramsci talk about the policies of the
party. Whenever one asked him about these, he answered without
hesitation: ‘I think the party’s line is correct.’ Yet his
analysis of the Italian situation implied it was not correct.
That made us uneasy, leaving us with a deep disillusion rather
than a stimulus to reflect and discuss. The obvious contrast
between the political line pursued by the party and the course
Gramsci proposed as the only effective way to fight fascism was
unacceptable to some of us, despite our respect and affection
for Gramsci.
Lo Sardo, who had contracted nephritis in jail, was
visibly declining.6 Aware of his condition, he
requested that he be allowed to die among his relatives. The
Ministry of the Interior, through the prison authorities, let
him know he could do so if he made an act of submission to the
regime. The disdain with which this comrade, who was then about
seventy-five, treated that reply surprised those of us who loved
him and would have forgiven him such an act, if it allowed him
to live a couple more years. Lo Sardo chose to stay in prison
and watch himself slowly die rather than ask for clemency. Lai,
who was closest to him, took care of him like a loving son, but
this could not be enough for someone as ill as Lo Sardo. At
times during our hours in the courtyard, I would call him to
play chequers with me, on a board we would draw on the stone
bench with a piece of brick, and purposely let him win. This
made Lo Sardo very happy because he took it to mean that his
mental faculties were not diminished. But that was not so.
Eventually he was taken to hospital, where this valiant fighter,
of a stainless loyalty to the working class, died. Tulli held a
memorial for him in the courtyard of the prison where Gramsci
and the rest of us stood in homage. Another fighter, the oldest
among us, had left us forever. His legacy was the battles he had
fought with an ardour typical of the noble land of Sicily, and
the example he set of how to uphold an idea for which he
sacrificed his life.
Soon after our discussions of the Italian political
situation, Bruno Tosin arrived in Turi di Bari. When a new
comrade entered our prison, he was always greeted as a messenger
from the outside world who for a few days brightened the life of
those sentenced before him. We wanted to know so many things and
ask so many questions, but above all we wanted news of what was
happening in Italy, of the work of the party, and of the
prospects for the fall of fascism. Tosin had been a party
functionary, who before his arrest had worked together with
Camilla Ravera in Turin. He was a well-trained comrade who had
followed a course in the Leninist school and served as a party
cadre for years. He could therefore give us important political
and economic information, tell us to what extent the party’s
policy was being applied by workers, what forces we had at our
disposal in the country, how the party saw the future of
fascism.
The information Tosin gave us was not that different
from what we already knew, but what astounded us was his claim
that the party expected the revolution by the end of the year.
We did not hide our disbelief in this flattering prediction, and
asked him to tell Gramsci what he had said to us. The following
day Gramsci, whom we had already alerted, met Tosin. He asked
Tosin when and where he had been arrested, how long his sentence
was, where he had been active before his arrest. As Tosin
answered these first questions, Gramsci’s expression became more
attentive, almost stern. Then he suddenly asked, ‘How many
active comrades were there in Turin and the province when you
were working there?’ Tosin thought a moment, then replied,
‘Perhaps a hundred.’ At this Gramsci’s face contracted in an
expression typical of him at a moment of severity. Without
further ado, he asked Tosin, taking his arm in a friendly
gesture, ‘So you wanted to make the revolution with that number
of communists?’ Tosin looked as if struck by an electric shock
and couldn’t answer. Gramsci was not the sort of comrade who,
after expressing a stern opinion (which in this case did not
just concern Tosin), would leave a comrade humiliated or
offended. He continued to talk to Tosin about different topics
as if nothing had occurred. But the expression on his face
suggested that he had not recovered his usual calm.
Gramsci’s analysis of the Italian and international
situation had split the comrades in Turi into two opposing camps
and triggered an intense, passionate discussion in our cells and
in the exercise yard. It was not unusual or abnormal for
comrades to have political discussions, nor did this surprise
the prison guards. But Gramsci took another view, fearing these
discussions would create actual fractions among us. Piacentini
and Ceresa must have encouraged this completely unfounded fear
by distorting our discussions, whose purpose was essentially to
clarify problems Gramsci had raised and about which none of us
had settled opinions. Thus just when we were preparing to put
some of our conclusions to Gramsci, he summoned us and said he
was suspending all further discussion for six months to prevent
the emergence of fractions. This announcement disappointed all
those who had heard Gramsci speak, because it denied us the
chance to continue a discussion that would have helped us
clarify our views on some aspects of the line Gramsci thought
the party ought to pursue, and certainly did not lessen
resentments brewing, especially among the youngest prisoners,
for reasons that were not always political. Was this the real
reason why Gramsci punished our group by depriving it of the
chance to discuss an issue about which he had said he wanted to
know what we thought?
In my view, the most probable explanation for his
decision lay in the state of his health, and the rule he had
given himself of following prison regulations to the letter, to
avoid being transferred to another section, or still worse sent
to another prison. This conjecture may seem illogical, but it is
entirely possible given Gramsci’s state of health at the time.
His insomnia had become more intense, even incurable, despite
strong doses of sedatives. The midnight inspection of our cells
woke him up and for the rest of the night he couldn’t fall
asleep again. The prison authorities took some measures to make
the inspections less noisy, but these were of little help. The
truth is that Gramsci’s health worsened day by day. The first
signs of this deterioration came when he repeatedly started to
cough up blood, against which the remedies available in prison
could do very little. Gramsci would have needed to be
transferred to a sanatorium in a supportive environment to have
a chance of recovering. Turi was not such a place, even though
he was able to receive medicines brought to him by his
sister-in-law Tatiana.
Moreover, sitting at a table for as many hours as he
did during the day worsened his physical condition. At times we
advised him to rest during the day, but he wouldn’t listen to
us. I consider myself, he said, at the editorial desk of L’Ordine
Nuovo and I need to write an article every day. The range of
topics he treated reflects that reply, in my view. Gramsci
certainly wished to provide or suggest original solutions for
Italian problems, to help the Italian movement move forward
politically along the lines that he had often indicated. His
discussion of problems of Fordism was in effect a reply to
positions adopted by the honourable comrade Riboldi in Turi di
Bari, who after reading a few books by Ford decided that Fordism
was tantamount to socialism.7 Since Riboldi was
writing a book on the subject there is no doubt that he prompted
Gramsci to compose what he probably would have said about it in L’Ordine
Nuovo. We could guess what Gramsci was writing, and why he
felt such a strong desire to write, but he offered no further
explanation. He told no-one about what he was actually writing.
He just said he was writing about Benedetto Croce, or the
function of intellectuals, or the Vatican, but without entering
into the problems he wanted to address in doing so. Did he
consider his comrades ill-equipped to discuss them, or was he
silent because he feared his work might be compromised by some
indiscretion that could reach the ears of the prison
authorities? I think the second hypothesis is closer to the
truth.
Objectively speaking, Gramsci did not trust any
comrade. Not that he thought anyone capable of reporting to the
authorities the actual content of what he was writing, which he
anyway sought to camouflage with elusive turns of phrase, and of
which few comrades even knew in the first place. It was because
the atmosphere in prison created systematic feelings of distrust
towards everything, especially in Gramsci’s case when his
general physical condition and state of health were so
precarious. Gramsci felt an absolute need to remain in Turi di
Bari and didn’t want to risk being transferred to another
prison. He was the head of the Communist Party and knew how
close was the surveillance which he was under and how many risks
he ran every day. Looked at this way, we can understand and
justify his diffidence towards men and things.
I was struck down by a fever the two doctors in the
prison diagnosed as typhoid. Since political prisoners could not
use the prison infirmary, the cell I shared with Riboldi and
Pertini had to do, though it lacked the most elementary means of
looking after a patient whose temperature was running at 40–1
degrees. With the approval of the prison authorities, Pertini
and Lai, to whom I owe so much for their affection, took it in
turns to look after me day and night, providing care which I
certainly would not have enjoyed in the prison infirmary.8 But
I lay ill for several months and my condition worsened every
day. Pertini had to argue with doctor Cisternino, who was the
Fascist Party secretary in Turi di Bari, and regularly expressed
surprise that I never became delirious despite sky-high
temperatures. This doctor, who stammered, had limited medical
knowledge, and was a mean-spirited and sectarian fascist to
boot. One morning he repeated his habitual refrain that I should
have fallen into delirium. ‘His mind continues to be clear,’ he
said. To which Pertini replied, ‘Clearer than yours.’ An
altercation ensued and Pertini all but ended up in solitary
confinement once again. The comrades in Turi, worried about my
state of health, asked the directorate of the prison to transfer
me to a hospital, but when the authorisation came from the
Ministry I was no longer in a fit state to be transported. I
could tell that my condition was critical because I kept
receiving visits from the local parish priest, though I had
neither called nor encouraged him, and from the chief warder who
every night came to see if I was still alive. The prison
authorities had already informed my family of my condition, so
all formalities were completed for my passage to the afterlife.
My family would not have been able to come from
Livorno to Turi di Bari had Pertini not secured the money for
them to make the trip. A friar, who was a friend of Pertini’s
mother and often came to Turi to see him and bring him news of
her, was entrusted with this mission and my family received the
means to come and see me. My sisters arrived in Turi accompanied
by a professor from the University of Bari recommended by
friends who lived there. It was this visit by my sisters that
cancelled my trip to the other world. In the presence of the two
prison doctors, the chief warder and my sisters, I received a
quick diagnosis that left everybody surprised, especially the
two doctors in charge of me. ‘What illness are you treating him
for?’ asked the professor. ‘Typhoid fever,’ mumbled the doctors.
The professor made a gesture of dismissal and said that the
graph of my temperature should have told them I had Malta fever.
Without further discussion he suggested how I should be cured.
No more ice (I consumed 18kg per day) nor enemas nor diet. They
must feed me immediately, starting with a fourth of an egg yolk
a day and progressively giving me more food. If there was a
garden, I should be taken out to breathe fresh air. The dear
professor, whose name I have forgotten, had plainly never been
to prison or he would have understood that certain privileges
are not granted to inmates.
Gramsci followed the progress of my illness with the
same anxiety and affection shown me by other comrades. One day
he peered at the small window in my cell door and stretched his
arm inside, passing me a small bouquet of flowers that he had
grown and picked in a little corner of the courtyard where we
exercised. ‘How are you?’ he asked, and after wishing me a
speedy recovery went back to his cell. This was an unusual
gesture for a man like Gramsci, who was not sentimental. But
prison, rather than stifling or drying up affections, encourages
their demonstration, especially towards comrades. It brings
together those who have been deprived of liberty to defend the
same idea, the same conception of the world. It is not true at
all that a need to defend one’s own life produces forms of
selfishness that extinguish solidarity, which a common life in
prison actually reinforces. My illness lingered a long time for
all the cures I underwent. My fever dropped, but did not
disappear, so that in the end I was transferred to another
prison where I could benefit from a radical change of climate.
Translated by Eleanor Chiari
NOTES
Preface
1See, among much else, the collections Gramsci in
Europa e in America, Bari 1995, and Gramsci in Asia e in
Africa, Cagliari 2010.
2‘Gramsci and Marxism in Britain’, New Left
Review I/176, July–August 1989, p. 71.
3See the essays collected in Western Marxism: A
Critical Reader, London 1978.
4Egemonia e democrazia. Gramsci e la questione
comunista nel dibattito di Mondoperaio, Rome 1977, pp.
33–91. Salvadori had just (1976) published what remains by far
the best study of Kautsky, translated into English in 1979 as Kautsky
and the Socialist Revolution, 1880–1938—a fundamental work;
Bobbio’s manifesto Quale socialismo? also appeared in
1976—translated into English a decade later as Which
Socialism?; Galli della Loggia would go on to produce the
most striking work on Italian national identity, L’identità
italiana (1996); Colletti, a member of the PCI from 1954 to
1964, had caused a considerable stir with the publication in
book form of an interview conducted with him by New Left
Review in 1974 (I/86, July–August 1974), which came out in
Italy a year later as Intervista politico-filosofica, and
was attacked in one of the PCI broadsides on the Mondoperaio symposium
as a tap-root of its mischief.
5See Guido Liguori, Gramsci Conteso.
Interpretazioni, dibattiti e polemiche 1922–2012, Rome 2012,
pp. 269–72. This creditably balanced account is the work of a
devoted member of the party, loyal to the memory of the PCI as
it once was.
6Amid the cross-currents of the time, individual
figures often changed positions. Colletti, in the decade from
1964 to 1974 an eloquent critic of the PCI from the left, had by
1977 moved close to the PSI on its right. On reading
‘Antinomies’, he wrote to me saying he thought well of it and
was recommending its publication in Italy with the house that
had produced his interview, but that he himself had decided that
it was necessary to rethink everything ab imis: letter,
1/6/1977. Much later, he would be elected to parliament on the
centre-right list led by Silvio Berlusconi.
7L’officina gramsciana. Ipotesi sulla struttura
dei ‘Quaderni del carcere’, Naples 1984: pp. 17–146 devoted
to the first task, pp. 149–228 to the second.
8Gramsci. Problemi di metodo, Rome 1997,
‘Impaginazione e analisi dei “Quaderni” ’, pp. 143–53.
9‘Quaderni del carcere di Antonio Gramsci’, in
Alberto Asor Rosa (ed.), Letteratura italiana, Vol IV,
Turin 1996, pp. 553–629. It is enough to compare Mordenti’s
analytic table and biographical comments, pp. 580–2 ff., with
Francioni’s appendix at pp. 137–46 to see the difference.
10Francioni’s pièce de résistance was the
objection that my treatment of three different usages of
‘hegemony’ in the Notebooks did not respect the order in
which they first appeared in them. In fact, since I remarked
that they were simultaneously at work in Gramsci’s writing
across the span of the notebooks, an analytic rather than a
diachronic account of them was logical.
11‘Oggi non troviamo più una sola delle indicazioni
politiche gramsciane alla base della politica complessiva del
Pci’. See Liguori, Gramsci conteso, p. 310.
12In an incident worthy of Balzac, out of whose
pages his successors could step, he was not even invited to the
sixtieth anniversary commemoration of Gramsci’s death. Born in
Sicily in 1919, Gerratana joined the Resistance in Rome at the
age of twenty-four, fighting in GAP (Gruppi di Azione
Patriottica) and helping to organise the reconstruction of the
PCI in the city. He was a friend and contemporary of Giaime
Pintor, one of the most gifted writers of his generation, killed
in 1943, whose posthumous collection Il sangue d’Europa Gerratana
edited and introduced in 1950. Anglophone readers can get a
sense of Gerratana’s qualities as an intellectual historian from
essays on Rousseau and Voltaire, Marx and Darwin, Lenin and
Stalin, Althusser and Heidegger, translated in New Left
Review, I/86, I/101–3, I/106, I/111. He died in 2000.
13Liguori, Gramsci conteso, pp. 337–43,
418–20: Francioni’s proposed alterations of Notebook 10
deprecated as a montage to change it from a critique of Croce
into one of Bukharin, to demonstrate Gramsci’s hostility to
Soviet Marxism in the time of Stalin.
14Leading contributions include: L’ultima ricerca
di Paolo Spriano, Rome 1988; Aldo Natoli, Antigone e il
prigionero, Rome 1991; Giuseppe Fiori, Gramsci, Togliatti, Stalin,
Rome 1991; Massimo Caprara, Gramsci e i suoi carcerieri,
Milan 2001; Angelo Rossi, Gramsci da eretico a icona,
Naples 2010; Luciano Canfora, Gramsci in carcere e il
fascismo, Rome-Salerno 2012; Giuseppe Vacca, Vita e
pensieri di Antonio Gramsci, 1926–1937, Turin 2012;
Franco Lo Piparo, I due carceri di Gramsci, Rome 2012 and
idem L’enigma del quaderno, Rome 2013; Mauro Canali, Il
tradimento, Venice 2013. In a different category is
Gerratana’s edition of Sraffa’s correspondence with Tatiana
Schucht, Lettere a Tania per Gramsci, Rome 1991.
15For examples, see The H-Word, pp. 80–1.
16Angelo d’Orsi (ed), Inchiesta su Gramsci.
Quaderni scomparsi, abiure, conversioni, tradimenti; leggenda o
verità?, Turin 2014. The term ‘post-communist’ generically
describes membership of the PCI in the time when it still
existed. In the great majority of cases, it has also come to
mean abandonment of any connexion with communism. But in this
volume, as elsewhere, there is a scattering of those who remain
faithful to ideals of the past, and averse to what the
Democratic Party—supposedly an heir of the PCI—has made of
these. Often they come from Rifondazione comunista, the now
small formation which resisted the self-dissolution of the PCI
in 1991: Raul Mordenti is a notable example in this collection.
A grotesque feature of much of the anti-communist literature is
the claim that it represents a form of history derived from
Carlo Ginzburg’s recommendation of clues as a heuristic
principle. From the opposite camp, Francioni had coquetted with
the same conceit: L’officina gramsciana, p. 23.
17‘Anderson’s error, as Francioni has demonstrated
…’, ‘Francioni has provided the following useful commentary …’,
‘As Francioni notes …’, ‘As Francioni has argued …’,
‘Francioni’s demonstration …’; ‘Buci-Gluckmann’s Gramsci and
the State can be read as an almost point-by-point implicit
refutation of Anderson’s arguments …’, ‘As Buci-Glucksmann
emphasises …’, ‘Modifying a phrase from Buci-Glucksmann …’, ‘As
originally proposed by Buci-Glucksmann …’, ‘As presciently noted
by Buci-Glucksmann …’, ‘As Buci-Glucksmann argues …’, ’As
Buci-Glucksmann notes …’: The Gramscian Moment. Philosophy,
Hegemony and Marxism, Leiden 2009, pp. 57, 81, 97, 116, 140,
220–1, 224, 238, 406.
18The Gramscian Moment p. 441.
19Ibid., pp. xx–xxi, 47, 80.
20Ibid., p. 441.
21Typical of the way politics features—or fails
to—in the book are such formulae as: ‘It is not our task here to
pass judgment on the complex political calculations that
prompted Togliatti …’; ‘Gramsci criticises what he sees, whether
fairly or not …’ etc.: The Gramscian Moment, pp. 105–6,
213.
22Simplicius’s sixth-century term for the
adjustments of Ptolemaic astronomy to anomalies in the heavens,
famously at issue in the fate of Galileo.
23Quaderni del carcere, II, Turin 1975, p.
1365.
24London version—‘Gramsci and Political Theory’, Marxism
Today, July 1977, pp. 205–13; Florence version—‘Gramsci and
Marxist Political Theory’, in Anne Showstack Sassoon (ed), Approaches
to Gramsci, London 1982, pp. 19–36; original in Politica
e storia in Gramsci, II, Rome 1977, pp. 37–51.
25‘Gramsci’, in How to Change the World: Tales of
Marx and Marxism, London 2011, pp. 314–33. Mysteriously—a
lapse of memory?—Hobsbawm sourced this chapter to the Florentine
address, and listed it as previously unpublished. The variance
between the two versions was a function of the audience.
Listeners in London needed an explanation of the particularities
of Italy that rendered a thinker like Gramsci possible,
unnecessary in Italy, while listeners in Italy were entitled to
more reconstruction of the political background of the Second
International and of Marxist arguments at large which Gramsci
confronted. Remarkably, neither version earns so much as a
mention by Thomas, whose copious bibliography finds room for
items by Nietzsche and Wittgenstein.
26Florence version, p. 28.
27London version, p. 211; How to Change the World,
p. 328.
28Florence version, p. 34.
29London version, p. 210; How to Change the World,
p. 327.
30Florence version, pp. 35–6.
31London version, p. 208; How to Change the World,
pp. 320–1, where there is one direct reference to myself, as
having reminded readers of Gramsci’s debt to debates in the
Comintern; another, criticizing my treatment of the idea of a
war of position, is dropped in his republication of the talk.
Though certainly reserved about ‘Antinomies’—political
differences aside, close textual analysis was not his cup of
tea—he did not resent application of its procedures to his own
work. Years later, of an essay I had written on his
autobiography and tetralogy, he said with a smile: ‘You’ve
deconstructed me, like Gramsci’.
32‘La guerra è la guerra’, Socialismo e fascismo.
L’Ordine Nuovo 1921–1922, Turin 1966, p. 58.
33Respectively: ‘Stato, partito, strumenti e
istituti dell’egemonia nei “Quaderni del carcere” ’, in Egemonia
Stato partito in Gramsci, pp. 37–53; ‘Gramsci come pensatore
rivoluzionario’, in Politica e Storia in Gramsci, II, pp.
69–99, and ‘Le forme dell’egemonia’ in Gramsci. Problemi di
metodo, pp. 119–26.
34Quaderni del carcere, III, p. 2011.
35Quaderni del carcere, II, p. 1319.
36Ibid., II, pp. 699–700, III, p. 1771.
37‘Due rivoluzioni’, in L’Ordine Nuovo 1919–1920,
Turin 1987, pp. 569–71—a fundamental text for his thought as a
whole.
38Quaderni del carcere, III, pp. 2283–4, p.
1863. The passage to which I drew attention in ‘Antinomies’
ascribed ‘statolatry’ in Soviet Russia to the proletariat’s lack
of any ‘long period of independent cultural and moral
development, capable of creating a civil society of its own,
before the conquest of power.’ See below, pp. 100, 114.
39See his contributions in the debate at the end of Egemonia
e democrazia, pp. 211, 216.
40A Zone of Engagement, London-New York 1992,
p. xi.
41‘Le ceneri di Gramsci’, Egemonia e democrazia,
pp. 69–91, its title taken from Pasolini’s poem of 1957. Today
the author is a leading editorialist in the Corriere della
sera.
1. Alteration
1See Tom Nairn, ‘The British Political Elite’, New
Left Review 23, January–February 1964; Perry Anderson,
‘Origins of the Present Crisis’, ibid.; Nairn, ‘The English
Working Class’, New Left Review 24, March–April 1964;
Nairn, ‘The Nature of the Labour Party’, New Left Review 27
and 28, September–October and November–December 1964; Anderson,
‘The Left in the Fifties’, New Left Review 29,
January-February 1965; Nairn, ‘Labour Imperialism’, New Left
Review 32, July–August 1965. Further developments of the
theses on English history and society contained in these initial
essays included: Anderson, ‘Socialism and Pseudo-Empiricism’, New
Left Review 35, January–February 1966; Anderson, ‘Components
of the National Culture’, New Left Review 50, July-August
1968; Nairn, ‘The Fateful Meridian’, New Left Review 60,
March–April 1970.
2The major response was the famous essay by Edward
Thompson, ‘The Peculiarities of the English’, The Socialist
Register 1965. Its criticisms probably won general assent on
the British left.
3Among the most notable examples of creative use of
Gramsci’s concept in recent works are: Eric Hobsbawm, The Age
of Capital, London 1975, pp. 249–50; Edward Thompson, Whigs
and Hunters, London 1975, pp. 262, 269; Raymond Williams,
‘Base and Superstructure’, NLR 82, November-December
1973—reworked in Marxism and Literature, London 1977;
Eugene Genovese, Roll, Jordan Roll, New York 1974, pp.
25–8.
4All references to Gramsci’s work will be to the Critical
Edition edited by Valentino Gerratana: Antonio Gramsci, Quaderni
del Carcere, Turin 1975, I–IV. Volumes I–III present for the
first time the complete and exact texts of the notebooks, in
their order of composition; Volume IV contains the critical
apparatus assembled by Gerratana, with admirable care and
discretion. The edition as a whole is a model of scholarly
scruple and clarity. Wherever the texts cited in this essay are
included in the English collection, Selections from the
Prison Notebooks, edited by Quintin Hoare and Geoffrey
Nowell-Smith, London 1971, references are also given to the
latter, and translations are usually taken from it, with
occasional modifications. The English editors provide far the
best informative apparatus available to any foreign-language
readership of Gramsci. Abbreviations will be QC and SPN respectively,
throughout.
5QC III, pp. 1614–6; SPN, pp. 234–5.
6QC II, pp. 865–6; SPN, pp. 236–8.
7Lettere dal Carcere, Turin 1965, p. 481.
8QC III, pp. 1566–7; SPN, pp. 242–3.
9Karl Marx, Surveys from Exile, London 1973,
pp. 238, 186.
10QC II, pp. 763–4; SPN, p. 263.
11QC III, pp. 1589–90; SPN, p. 160.
12See, for representative examples, Norberto Bobbio,
‘Gramsci e la concezione della società civile’, in the
symposium Gramsci e la Cultura Contemporanea, Rome 1969,
p. 94; and more recently, Maria-Antonietta Macciocchi, Pour
Gramsci, Paris 1974, p. 140.
13G.V. Plekhanov, Izbrannye Filosofskie
Proizvedeniya, I, Moscow 1956, p. 372.
14Plekhanov, Sochineniya, (ed. Ryazanov),
Moscow 1923, II, pp. 55, 63, 77; III, p. 91.
15Sochineniya, II, p. 347.
16P. Axelrod, K Voprosu o Sovremennykh Zadachykh
i Taktik Russkikh Sotsial-Demokratov, Geneva 1898, pp. 20,
26.
17Axelrod, Istoricheskoe Polozhenie i Vzaimnoe
Otnoshenie Liberalnoi i Sotsialisticheskoi Demokratii v Rossii,
Geneva 1898, p. 25.
18Axelrod, K Voprosu, p. 27.
19Perepiska G.V. Plekhanova i P.B. Akselroda,
Moscow 1925, II, p. 142.
20Y. Martov, ‘Vsegda v Menshinstve. O Sovremennykh
Zadachakh Russkoi Sotsialisticheskoi Intelligentsii’, Zarya,
Nos. 2–3, December 1901, p. 190.
21Lenin, Collected Works, Vol. 34, p. 56.
22A. Potresov, ‘Nashi Zakliucheniya. O Liberalizme i
Gegemonii’, Iskra, No. 74, 20 November 1904.
23Lenin, Collected Works, Vol. 17, pp. 231–2.
24I have elsewhere discussed the importance of these
polemics of 1911, for an account of the nature of Tsarism, in Lineages
of the Absolutist State, London 1975, pp. 354–5.
25Lenin, Collected Works, Vol. 17, pp. 232–3.
See also pp. 78–9.
26Ibid., pp. 57–8.
27Trotsky, History of the Russian Revolution,
I, London 1965, pp. 296–7.
28Manifestes, thèses et résolutions des quatre
premiers congrès mondiaux de l’Internationale Communiste
1919–1923, Paris 1969 (reprint), p. 20.
29Ibid., pp. 45, 61.
30Ibid., p. 171.
31QC III, p. 1591; SPN, p. 161.
32QC III, p. 1584; SPN, pp. 181–2.
33QC III, pp. 1612–13; SPN, p. 168.
34QC III, p. 1612; SPN, p. 168. It
will be remembered that the Potresov specifically denounced any
interpretation of hegemony that involved an ‘assimilation’ of
allied classes.
35QC III, p. 1576; SPN, pp. 169–70.
36QC III, p. 2010; SPN, p. 57.
37QC III, p. 2011; SPN, p. 58.
38Lettere dal Carcere, p. 616.
39QC II, p. 691; SPN, p. 271.
40QC III, pp. 1518–19; SPN, p. 12. The
context is precisely a discussion of intellectuals.
41Lettere del Carcere, p. 481.
42QC III, p. 1638; SPN, p. 80n.
43QC II, p. 752; SPN, p. 246.
44QC II, pp. 810–11; SPN, p. 239.
2. Variants
1QC II, p. 763; SPN, p. 170.
2‘The worldwide experience of bourgeois and
landowner governments has evolved two methods of keeping people
in subjection. The first is violence,’ with which the Tsars
‘demonstrated to the Russian people the maximum of what can and
cannot be done’ Lenin wrote. ‘But there is another method, best
developed by the British and French bourgeoisie … the method of
deception, flattery, fine phrases, promises by the million,
petty sops, and concessions of the unessential while retaining
the essential.’ Collected Works, Vol. 24, pp. 63–4.
3The first major interpretation of Gramsci of this
sort was the work of a PSI theorist: Giuseppe Tamburrano, Antonio
Gramsci. La vita, il pensiero, l’azione, Bari 1963.
4For a representative version of these ideas, see
Perry Anderson, ‘Problems of Socialist Strategy’, in the
collection Towards Socialism, London 1965, pp. 223–47.
5In other words, it is quite wrong simply to
designate parliament an ‘ideological apparatus’ of bourgeois
power without further ado. The ideological function of
parliamentary sovereignty is inscribed in the formal framework
of every bourgeois constitution, and is always central to the
cultural dominion of capital. However, parliament is also, of
course, a ‘political apparatus’, vested with real attributes of
debate and decision, which are in no sense a mere subjective
trick to lull the masses. They are objective structures of a
once-great—still potent—historical achievement, the triumph of
the ideals of the bourgeois revolution.
6Nicos Poulantzas, Political Power and Social
Classes, London 1973, p. 217.
7Ernest Mandel, Late Capitalism, London 1975,
p. 501.
8See the stimulating comments in Göran Therborn,
‘What does the Ruling Class do when it Rules?’, The Insurgent
Sociologist, Vol. VI, No. 3, Spring 1976.
9A real and central belief in popular sovereignty
can, in other words, coexist with a profound scepticism towards
all governments that juridically express it. The divorce between
the two is typically mediated by the conviction that no
government could be otherwise than distant from those it
represents, yet many are not representative at all. This is not
a mere fatalism or cynicism among the masses in the West. It is
an active assent to the familiar order of bourgeois democracy,
as the dull maximum of liberty, that is constantly reproduced by
the radical absence of proletarian democracy in the East, whose
regimes figure the infernal minimum. There is no space to
explore the effects of fifty years of Stalinism here: their
importance is enormous for understanding the complex historical
meaning of bourgeois democracy in the West today.
10QC II, pp. 1236–7.
11QC I, p. 443.
12QC II, p. 1049. See also QC III, p.
1570; SPN, p. 246.
13‘Politics as a Vocation’, in From Max Weber,
ed. Gerth and Mills, London 1948, p. 78.
14This is a regulative principle of any modern
capitalist state. It naturally permits of certain variations and
qualifications in practice. The state’s monopoly of the means of
coercion may be legally drawn at the line of automatic weapons,
rather than handguns, as in the USA or Switzerland. There may be
semi-legal organisations of private violence, such as the
American goon-squads of the twenties and thirties. Gramsci was
certainly impressed by the existence of the latter. However,
these phenomena have always been of marginal importance compared
with the central machinery of the state, in the advanced
capitalist social formations.
15QC I, p. 121; SPN, p. 232.
16QC II, pp. 808–9.
17QC I, pp. 279–80.
18QC III, p. 1566; SPN, p. 242.
19QC II, p. 801; SPN, p. 261.
20QC III, p. 1590; SPN, p. 160.
21QC III, p. 2303; SPN, p. 261.
22For Marx, London 1970, p. 110.
23Marx, Surveys from Exile, p. 186. ‘The
Civil War in France’ is the pendant work that provides a theory
of the diametric opposite of Bonapartism: ‘The direct antithesis
to the Empire was the Commune … The unity of the nation was not
to be broken, but, on the contrary, to be organised by the
Communal constitution and to become a reality by the destruction
of the state power which claimed to be the embodiment of that
unity independent of, and superior to, the nation itself … its
legitimate functions were to be wrested from an authority
usurping pre-eminence over society itself, and restored to the
responsible agents of society.’ Marx, The First International
and After, London 1974, pp. 208, 210. The ‘Critique of the
Gotha Programme’ repeats the same contrast: ‘Freedom consists in
converting the State from an organ superimposed on society into
one thoroughly subordinate to it.’ (ibid, p. 354). The term
‘civil society’ is abbreviated to ‘society’ in Marx’s later
work, in all probability because of the ambiguity of the German bürgerliche
Gesellschaft, but it clearly occupies the same structural
position in these contrasts between state and society.
24QC II, p. 1253; SPN, p. 208.
25For successive usages of the term, from the
Enlightenment onwards, see Bobbio, ‘Gramsci e la concezione
della società civile’, op. cit., pp. 80–4. Prior to Hegel,
‘civil society’ was customarily opposed to ‘natural society’ or
‘primitive society’, as civilisation to nature, rather than to
‘political society’ or ‘state’, as divisions within
civilisation.
26Lenin and Philosophy and other essays,
London 1971, pp. 136–7. Althusser commented: ‘To my knowledge,
Gramsci is the only one who went any distance down the road I am
taking … Unfortunately, Gramsci did not systematise his
intuitions, which remained in the state of acute but fragmentary
notes.’
27Lenin and Philosophy, pp. 137–8. Once this
argument is accepted, of course, there is no reason why not only
bourgeois newspapers or families but also capitalist factories
and offices should not be dubbed ‘State apparatuses’—a
conclusion at which Althusser, to his credit, evidently baulked.
(Nothing would be easier thereafter than to announce the
identity of the ‘State bourgeoisie’ in the USSR and the
bourgeoisie in the USA.) This omission, however, merely serves
to suggest the lack of seriousness of the whole trope.
28See the perceptive remarks in Isaac Deutscher’s
interview on the Cultural Revolution, La Sinistra, Vol.
1, No. 2, November 1966, pp. 13–16.
29‘The Capitalist State: A Reply to Nicos
Poulantzas’, New Left Review 59, January–February 1970,
p. 59. Poulantzas, however, can certainly not be charged with
indifference to the problem of the fascist state. His remarkable
work, Fascism and Dictatorship, London 1974, represents a
rare example of theoretical and empirical synthesis in
contemporary Marxist literature. While retaining the etiquette
of ‘Ideological State Apparatuses’ in vogue at the time,
Poulantzas nevertheless argued that ‘this in no way means that
the “private” or “public” character of the Ideological State
Apparatuses is of no importance’, and sought to define the
specificity of the fascist state by its reorganisation of the
respective branches of the state apparatus into a new and more
centralised pattern (pp. 305, 315–30). If his account of the
latter remains finally insufficient, it is because his general
explanation of the nature of fascism suffers from a certain
historical under-determination. Internally, it tends to minimise
the acuity of the class threat from the proletariat that evoked
it (working class defeat is held to have preceded fascist
victory in Italy and Germany—in which case fascism would have
been supererogatory for the bourgeoisie), while externally it
neglects the dynamics of inter-imperialist struggle (the Second
World War is omitted altogether, and with it decisive
revelations of the social nature and rationale of fascist
expansionism). A more drastic theoretical delimitation of the
fascist states from the bourgeois democracies would follow from
any study of these determinants. Given their absence, however,
the scope and quality of Poulantzas’s work remain all the more
impressive.
30QC III, p. 1302. The same idea is cited in QC II,
p. 858; QC II, p. 1087; QCII, pp. 1223–4. Gramsci
objected to Croce’s undue generalisation of his thesis, but he
accepted its validity as a principle. ‘The claim is not
paradoxical for the theory of State-hegemony-moral
consciousness, because it can in fact happen that the moral and
political direction of a country in a given epoch is not
exercised by the legal government, but by a “private”
organisation or even a revolutionary party.’
31QC III, pp. 1707–8; SPN, pp. 253–4.
32QC III, p. 2058.
33QC III, p. 2287; SPN, p. 540.
3. Asymmetry
1The caution should be repeated. The dualist
analysis to which Gramsci’s notes typically tend does not permit
an adequate treatment of economic constraints that act directly
to enforce bourgeois class power: among others, the fear of
unemployment or dismissal that can, in certain historical
circumstances, produce a ‘silenced majority’ of obedient
citizens and pliable voters among the exploited. Such
constraints involve neither the conviction of consent, nor the
violence of coercion. Their importance has, it is true,
diminished with the post-war consolidation of bourgeois
democracies in the West, compared with the role of earlier
patronage or cacique systems. However, their lesser forms remain
myriad in the day-to-day workings of a capitalist society.
Another mode of class power that escapes Gramsci’s main typology
is corruption—consent by purchase, rather than by persuasion,
without any ideological fastening. Gramsci was, of course, by no
means unaware of either ‘constraint’ or ‘corruption’. He
thought, for example, that political liberties in the USA were
largely negated by ‘economic pressures’ (QC III, p.
1666); while in France during the Third Republic, he noted that
‘between consent and force stood corruption/fraud,’ or the
neutralisation of movements of opposition by bribery of their
leaders, characteristic of conjunctures in which the use of
force was too risky (QC III, p. 1638; SPN, p.
80n). However, he never intercalated them to form a more
sophisticated spectrum of concepts systematically into his main
theory. The comments below deliberately remain within the
confines of the latter.
2QC I, p. 123; SPN, p. 230.
3These formulations deliberately remain within the
purview of Gramsci’s concepts. They involve one major
simplification, characteristic of the Prison Notebooks—the
elision of the ‘cultural’ and ‘political’ dimensions of popular
consent to the rule of capital. The two cannot, however, be
straightforwardly equated. No bourgeois parliament was ever
merely a secular simulacrum of a religious church. (See footnote
at p. 65 above.) It can be said that Gramsci’s attention always
tended more towards the purely cultural institutions for
securing the consent of the masses—churches, schools, newspapers
and so on—than to the specifically political institutions which
assure the stability of capitalism, with their necessarily
greater complexity and ambiguity. For the purposes of the
argument above, the indeterminacy characteristic of Gramsci’s
discussions of consent has been retained.
4Talcott Parsons, with a characteristic mélange of
insight and confusion, once advanced a comparison between power
and money of a very different sort, mystifying any analogy by
drawing the inimitable conclusion that a ‘democratic political
system’ can increase the total amount of classless ‘power’ in a
society by ‘votes’ in the same way that a banking system can
increase purchasing power by ‘credit’ (votes do ‘double duty’,
like dollars in a bank, in his phrase). See ‘On the Concept of
Political Power’, Proceedings of the American Philosophical
Society, June 1963, now republished in Sociological
Theory and Modern Society, New York 1967.
5Or to stronger foreign currencies, with a superior
ratio to gold.
6A classical example of such a sudden disappearance
of ‘limits’ is provided by the commentaries and refutations
inserted by typographical workers in bourgeois newspapers during
a revolutionary situation. In Russia and Cuba alike, compositors
retorted to the propaganda of the capitalist press in its own
pages, by appending what the Cuban workers called ‘tails’ to the
more mendacious articles contained in it. The cultural control
system was thereby sprung into the air the moment the ‘rights’
of private property were defied, because there was no stable
state apparatus of repression to enforce them. Trotsky commented
on this structural relationship, in his account of the situation
in Russia after the February Revolution: ‘How about the force of
property? said the petty-bourgeois socialists, answering the
Bolsheviks. Property is a relation among people. It represents
an enormous power so long as it is universally acknowledged and
supported by that system of compulsion called Law and the State.
But the very essence of the present situation was that the old
State had suddenly collapsed, and the entire old system of
rights had been called into question by the masses. In the
factories the workers were more and more regarding themselves as
proprietors, and the bosses as uninvited guests. Still less
assured were the feelings of the landlords in the provinces,
face to face with those surly vengeful muzhiks, and far
from that governmental power in whose existence they did for a
time, owing to their distance from the capital, believe. The
property-holders, deprived of the possibility of using their
property, or protecting it, ceased to be real property-holders
and became badly frightened philistines who could not give any
support to the government for the simple reason that they needed
it themselves.’ History of the Russian Revolution, I, p.
197.
7The greatest achievement of Gramsci’s thought in
prison—his theory of intellectuals, which produced the most
sustained single text in the Notebooks—is perforce
omitted altogether from this essay. Suffice it to say that in
this field, Gramsci’s historical exploration of the complexities
of European societies had, and has, no equal within Marxism.
8QC III, pp. 2010–11; SPN, pp. 57–8.
9Lenin, Collected Works, Vol. 28, pp. 252–3;
Trotsky, Literature and Revolution, Michigan 1966, pp.
184–200.
10Thus in one fragment he argued that in the
necessary absence of cultural superiority, the working class
would initially have to rely to excess on political command,
producing the phenomenon of what he called statolatry. ‘For some
social groups, which before their ascent to autonomous State
life have not had a long independent period of cultural and
moral development on their own (such as was made possible in
mediaeval society and under the Absolute regimes by the
juridical existence of privileged Estates or orders), a period
of statolatry is necessary and indeed opportune. This
“statolatry” is nothing other than the normal form of “State
life”, or at least initiation to autonomous State life and the
creation of a “civil society” which it was not historically
possible to create before the ascent to independent State
life.’ QCII, p. 1020; SPN, p. 268.
11QC II, p. 1316; QC II, p. 1227; SPN,
p. 119.
12QC II, p. 1222.
13QC II, p. 691; SPN, p. 271.
14QC II, p. 1235.
15QC II, p. 1235. See also Lettere dal
Carcere, p. 616, for the same comparison.
16QC II, p. 1223. Elsewhere, Gramsci compared
Croce—‘the greatest Italian prose-writer since Manzoni’—to
Goethe, for his ‘serenity, composure and imperturbability.’ Lettere
dal Carcere, p. 612.
17For an analysis of the sliding structures of
Machiavelli’s thought, and their relation to the political
setting of Renaissance Italy, see Lineages of the Absolute
State, pp. 163–8. The dualist cast of Gramsci’s political
theory descended directly from Machiavelli, for whom ‘arms’ and
‘laws’ were naturally exhaustive of power—two centuries before
the emergence of economic theory in Europe, and three before the
advent of historical materialism. Gramsci’s return to the
voluntarist categories of the Renaissance necessarily bypassed
the problem of economic constraints.
18Lukács and Gorter were examples, among others.
19For a full-length discussion, see Lineages of
the Absolutist State, pp. 345–60.
20Lenin, Collected Works, Vol. 17, pp.
114–15, 146, 153, 187, 233–41; Vol. 18, pp. 70–77; Vol. 24, pp.
44,
21QC III, p. 1666.
22QC III, p. 1636; SPN, p. 80n.
23Protokoll der Erweiterten Exekutive der
Kommunistischen Internationale, February–March 1926, Hamburg
1926, p. 126. Note that the French version of this speech in Correspondence
Internationale, 13 March 1926, was much abridged. Bordiga
went on to make an eloquent indictment of the demagogic
ouvrierism and organisational inquisitions under way in the
Third International by that date.
4. Contexts
1Georg Lukács, Lenin, London 1970, p. 12.
2‘Der Krise der Kommunistischen Internationale
und der Dritte Kongress’, Editorial in Kommunismus,
15 June 1921, p. 691.
3‘Spontaneität der Massen, Aktivität der Partei’, Die
Internationale, III 8, 1921, pp. 213–14. For an English
text, see Georg Lukács, Political Writings 1919–1929,
London 1972, p. 102.
4‘Spontaneität der Massen, Aktivität der Partei’,
p. 215; Political Writings, p. 104.
5Trotsky, ‘The Main Lessons of the Third Congress’,
in The First Five Years of the Communist International,
I, New York 1945, pp. 295–6.
6QC II, p. 1229; SPN, p. 120.
7QC II, p. 866; SPN, p. 237.
8Lenin, Collected Works, Vol. 32, pp. 474–5,
471, 474.
9Lenin, Collected Works, Vol. 32, p. 476.
10Hans Delbrück, Über den Kampf Napoleons mit dem
alten Europa, later expanded into Über die
Verschiedenheit der Strategie Friedrichs und Napoleons,
Berlin 1881. The remote inspiration for Delbrück’s theory was
the postscript note in Book 8 of Clausewitz’s Vom Kriege (from
1827), where Clausewitz discussed the case of wars with a
‘limited aim’, which therefore departed from his general schema
that the aim of war was the ‘overthrow’ of the enemy. See
Clausewitz, Vom Kriege, Bonn 1952, pp. 882–906.
11The first three volumes appeared in 1900, 1901 and
1907 successively. The fourth volume was published after the
war, in 1920. For the ‘two strategies’, see especially Vol. 1,
pp. 123–7, and Vol. IV, pp. 333–63. Otto Hintze wrote the most
effective criticism of Delbrück’s account of Frederick II’s
military practice.
12See ‘Eine Geschichte der Kriegskunst’, now
in Franz Mehring, Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. 8, Berlin
1967, devoted to his military writings and entitled Kriegsgeschichte
und Militärfrage, p. 135.
13Ibid., pp. 147–50, 200.
14The polemic between Kautsky and Luxemburg took the
form of a sequence of lengthy exchanges in Die Neue Zeit in
1910. These were, in order: Kautsky, ‘Was nun?’ 8 April,
pp. 35–40, 15 April, pp. 65–80; Luxemburg, ‘Ermattung oder
Kampf?’ 27 May, pp. 257–66, 3 July, pp. 291–305; Kautsky, ‘Eine
neue Strategie’, 17 June, pp. 364–74, 24 June, pp. 412–21;
Luxemburg, ‘Die Theorie und die Praxis’, 22 July, pp.
564–78, 29 July, pp. 626–42; Kautsky, ‘Zwischen Baden und
Luxemburg’, 5 August, pp. 652–67; Luxemburg, ‘Zur
Richtigstellung’, 19 August, pp. 756–60; Kautsky, ‘Schlusswort’,
19 August, pp. 760–65. It should be emphasised that Kautsky
nowhere attributed his categories to Delbrück, whom he cited
only once in the entire polemic, in a passing reference to
ancient history. Luxemburg, consequently, seems to have remained
unaware of the source of Kautsky’s ideas to the end.
15Delbrück expressly equated a ‘strategy of
attrition’ (Ermattungsstrategie) with a ‘war of position’
(Stellungskrieg), during the First World War. He
advocated the latter for the German struggle in the West, by
contrast with Schlieffen.
16‘Was nun?’ p. 38. Compare Gramsci’s text
cited on pp. 39–4 above.
17‘Eine neue Strategie’, p. 369.
18Ibid.
19Ibid., p. 370.
20Ibid., p. 374.
21‘Was Nun?’ pp. 37–8. Kautsky, of course,
knew of the existence of the Fabian Society, but appears to have
forgotten the revealing coincidence of eponymous hero.
22QC III, pp. 1613–14; SPN, p. 233.
23‘Die Theorie und die Praxis’, p. 576.
24Ibid., p. 572.
25Ibid.
26‘Ermattung oder Kampf?’ pp. 294–5.
27Luxemburg, of course, always asserted the need for
proletarian insurrection to achieve socialism: but she tended to
merge it into vaster ongoing waves of working class militancy,
in which its incommensurability was obscured.
28L. Martov, ‘Die preussische Diskussion und die
russische Erfahrung’, Die Neue Zeit, 16 September
1910, pp. 907–19.
29Ibid., pp. 907, 913, 919.
30J. Karsky (Marchlewski), ‘Ein Missverstandnis’, Die
Neue Zeit, 28 October 1910, p. 102.
31Lenin, Collected Works, Vol. 34, pp. 427–8.
Martov, in Lenin’s angry phrase, was ‘“deepening” (botching)
Kautsky,’ by denying the applicability of a Niederwerfungsstrategie to
the year 1905 in Russia (p. 427). Actually, Kautsky’s comments
on what he termed the ‘policy of violence’ of the Russian
proletariat in 1905–6 had evinced a thinly disguised lack of
enthusiasm. Martov’s reading of them was thus not far from the
mark.
32‘Zwischen Baden und Luxemburg’, p. 665.
There is no space here to go into the history of the ‘defence
clause’—now standard in the official documents of the heirs of
the Third International. Suffice it to say that it was a common
patrimony of the classical parties of the Second International.
Bebel, Turati and Bauer all devoted major speeches to it, at
respective party congresses of the SPD, PSI and OSPD.
33QC II, p. 802; SPN, p. 239.
34Lenin, Collected Works, Vol. 16, p. 383.
This article contains the formal reply that Lenin drafted for
publication in Die Neue Zeit, in answer to Martov’s use
of Kautsky’s ‘strategy of attrition’, during the composition of
which he wrote his letter to Marchlewski. The article was
refused by Kautsky and never printed in Germany.
35QC III, p. 1616; SPN, p. 236. To
Quintin Hoare belongs the credit of having first seen the
significance of this passage, in his editing of the political
sections of Selections from the Prison Notebooks. Gramsci
was referring to Trotsky’s speech to the Fourth World Congress
of the Comintern in 1922.
36QC II, p. 973. QC III, p. 1636; SPN,
p. 80n.
37QC II, p. 802; SPN, p. 239. It has
sometimes been thought that this passage refers to the fascist,
rather than to the communist, movement. A careful study of it
seems to exclude this hypothesis. The ‘enormous sacrifices’ made
by the ‘masses’ are unmistakably a reference to the working
class. Similarly, Gramsci would never have regarded fascism as
definitively victorious in Italy—which its installation in
power, in the context of this paragraph, would have made it. In
general, the emphasis on ultra-centralised authority and
discipline here should probably be linked to the (otherwise
enigmatic) call for the ‘sole command’ of a proletarian Foch in
the major text on East and West: QC II, p. 866; SPN,
p. 238.
38‘Ermattungstaktik war’s, was dir behagte’
(‘Tactics of attrition are what you enjoyed’): ‘An Walter
Benjamin’, in Bertolt Brecht, Gesammelte Werke, Vol. X,
Frankfurt 1967, p. 828. Brecht had few illusions in the
practical efficacy of his friend’s perspective: ‘Der Feind,
der dich von deinem Büchern jagte / Lässt sich von unsereinem
nicht ermatten’ (‘The enemy who drives you from your books /
Will not be worn away by the likes of us’).
39For the text of the Athos Lisa Report, see
pp. 156–68 below. In it, Gramsci discusses the military problems
of a future Italian revolution with a notable technical and
organisational precision.
40QC I, p. 120; SPN, p. 231.
41‘On the United Front’, in The First Five Years
of the Communist International, Vol. II, New York, 1953, pp.
91–104.
42For Gramsci’s views, see Paolo Spriano, Storia
del Partito Communista Italiano, Vol. II, Turin 1969, pp.
262–74. Trotsky’s analyses of the Italian situation are to be
found in Writings of Leon Trotsky 1929 and 1930 New
York 1975; and 1930–1931, New York 1973. They are
collected and discussed in Silvio Corvisieri, Trotskij e il
Communismo Italiano, Rome 1969, pp. 326–35.
43Voina Klassov, Moscow 1921, p. 55.
44Theses submitted to the Eleventh Party Congress of
the CPSU.
45Voina Klassov, p. 105.
46Military Writings, New York 1969, p. 47.
47Ibid., p. 25.
48Ibid., p. 85.
49Ibid., pp. 65, 88.
50Ibid., p. 54.
51Ibid., pp. 84–5. Trotsky was careful to go on
immediately to say that this did not mean that military struggle
between classes in the West could ever be described as a sheer
‘war of position’. For ‘Generally speaking, there cannot even be
talk of some sort of absolute positionalism, all the more so in
a civil war. In question here is the reciprocal relation between
the elements of manoeuvrability and positionalism’: p. 85.
5. Implications
1‘Of course, unless the revolution assumes a mass
character and affects the troops, there can be no question of
serious struggle. That we must work among the troops goes
without saying. But we must not imagine that they will come over
to our side at one stroke, as a result of persuasion or their
own convictions. The Moscow uprising clearly demonstrated how
stereotyped and lifeless this view is. As a matter of fact, the
wavering of the troops which is inevitable in every truly
popular movement, leads to a real fight for the troops whenever
the revolutionary struggle becomes acute.’ Lenin, Collected
Works, Vol. 11, p. 174.
2Where Is Britain Going?, London 1973, p. 87.
Annexe: Athos Lisa’s Report
1Athos Lisa, Memorie. Dall’ergastolo di Santo
Stefano alla Casa penale di Turi di Bari, Milan 1973, with
preface by Terracini.
2Illustrated, respectively, by Gianni Francioni, L’officina
gramsciana, Naples 1984, passim, for which see above
pp. 7–8; Angelo Rossi, Gramsci da eretico a icona, Naples
2010, pp. 95–115; Giuseppe Vacca, Vita e pensieri di Antonio
Gramsci, Turin 2012, pp. 120–2 ff, for which see The
H-Word, p. 81 n5.
3The merit of finally bringing this history to light
belongs to Ruggero Giacomini, whose fine study Il giudice e
il prigionero, Rome 2014, includes the fullest and best
account, from a variety of witnesses, of Gramsci’s years and
views in prison. For his determination that fascists be struck
off the rolls of a Constituent Assembly, see the testimony of
Ercole Piacentini in Cesare Bermani, Gramsci, gli
intelletuali e la cultura proletaria, Milan 2007.
4Lisa’s report follows, omitting a couple of initial
sentences in which he noted that he was writing from memory two
years after the event, so could not guarantee recalling every
argument in Gramsci’s complex thought, but had given as accurate
and objective account of it as was in his power.
5Here ends the report by Lisa published in Rinascita.
6Francesco Lo Sardo (1871–1931): Socialist militant
from Sicily, who became the first communist deputy for the
island in 1924.
7Ezio Riboldi: former Socialist deputy in the
Italian Parliament, who joined the Communist Party and was
imprisoned in the twenties; amnestied and expelled from the PCI
in 1933.
8Sandro Pertini (1896–1990): Socialist who went on
to play a leading role in the resistance, becoming a deputy and
senator for the PSI after the war, and eventually president of
the republic (1978–1985). Giovanni Lai: Sardinian communist,
active in Cagliari and member of the Central Committee after the
war.
INDEX
Adorno, Theodor 3
Althusser, Louis 3, 9, 75, 77–80, 87
Andreotti, Giulio 4
Axelrod, Pavel 44–6, 50
Balzac, Honoré de 9, 12
Bauer, Otto 12
Bebel, August 129
Benjamin, Walter 134–5
Berlusconi, Silvio 7
Bermani, Cesare 155
Bernstein, Eduard 110
Bobbio, Norberto 5, 27, 43, 77
Bordiga, Amadeo 105–6, 116, 148
Brecht, Bertolt 134–5
Buci-Glucksmann, Christine 8, 11–12
Bukharin, Nikolai 10, 105–6
Canali, Mauro 10
Canfora, Luciano 10
Caprara, Massimo 10
Carducci, Giosuè 99
Carrillo, Santiago 4
Ceresa, Giuseppe 164, 170
Clausewitz, Carl von 119–20
Colletti, Lucio 5–8
Corvisieri, Silvio 137
Craxi, Bettino 4
Croce, Benedetto 10, 26, 30, 55, 69, 81–2, 96–9, 172
Darwin, Charles 9
Davidson, Donald 14
Debray, Régis 149
Delbrück, Hans 119–21, Deutscher, Issac 78
d’Orsi, Angelo 11
Engels, Friedrich 37, 71, 143
Fabius Cunctator 124–5
Ferguson, Adam 77
Fiori, Giuseppe 10
Foch, Ferdinand 36, 133
Forgacs, David 2
Francioni, Gianni 7–13, 154
Frederick II 119
Frölich, Paul 110–11
Frunze, Mikhail 137–8
Galileo Galilei 14
Galli della Loggia, Ernesto 4–5, 25–7
Garibaldi, Giuseppe 122
Genovese, Eugene 32
Gerratana, Valentino 3, 7, 9, 21–2, 24–5, 33
Giacomini, Ruggero 155
Ginzburg, Carlo 11
Giolitti, Giovanni 166
Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von 99
Gorter, Herman 101
Gramsci, Antonio passim
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 12, 30, 75, 77, 98
Heidegger, Martin 9
Hintze, Otto 120
Hoare, Quintin 1, 33, 132
Hobbes, Thomas 14
Hobsbawm, Eric 15–21, 25, 32
Kant, Immanuel 77, 99
Kautsky, Karl 5, 30, 119, 121–31, 135, 143
Krasnov, Peter 34, 36, 114
Lai, Giovanni 164, 168, 173
Lassalle, Ferdinand 122
Lenin, Vladimir 9, 17, 21, 30, 36, 38, 43, 45–50,
61–2, 94–5, 98, 104, 113–15, 125, 127–31, 133, 135–7, 145, 148
Liguori, Guido 6, 8, 10
Lisa, Athos 13, 28, 135–6, 151–75
Lo Piparo, Franco 10
Lo Sardo, Francesco 164, 168–9
Locke, John 77
Lukács, Georg 25, 101, 110–11, 130, 137–8, 143, 148
Luxemburg, Rosa 38, 119, 121, 124–9, 143, 148
Macciocchi, Maria-Antonietta 43
Machiavelli, Niccolò 1, 14, 17, 30, 54, 100–1
Macis, Enrico 155
Mandel, Ernest 67
Manzoni, Alessandro 99
Marchlewski, Julian 127–8, 131
Martov, Julius 45, 50, 127–8, 129, 131
Marx, Karl 9, 17, 30, 37, 40–1, 43, 75–7, 87, 98,
102, 130, 135, 143
Mehring, Franz 120
Miliband, Ralph 79
Mordenti, Raul 11
Moretti, Franco 25
Mussolini, Benito 117, 155
Nairn, Tom 31–2
Napoleon, Louis 41, 119
Natoli, Aldo 10
Nicholas II 102
Nietzsche, Friedrich 16
Nowell-Smith, Geoffrey 1, 33
Parsons, Talcott 88–9
Pasolini, Pier Paolo 27
Pertini, Sandro 173, 174
Piacentini, Ercole 164, 170
Pintor, Giaime 9
Plekhanov, Georgi 30, 44–6
Potresov, Alexander 46, 50, 52
Poulantzas, Nicos 67, 79–80
Ravera, Camilla 169
Renzi, Matteo 154
Riboldi, Ezio 172–3
Robespierre, Maximilien 99
Rossi, Angelo 10, 154
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques 9, 14, 77
Ryazanov, David 44
Salvadori, Massimo 4–5, 24–6
Sartre, Jean-Paul 3
Schiavone, Aldo 8
Schlieffen, Alfred von 120–1
Schucht, Tatiana 10, 171
Scucchia, Angelo 164
Showstack Sassoon, Anne 16
Simplicius 14
Spadoni, Bruno 164
Smith, Adam 30
Sraffa, Piero 10
Stalin, Joseph 9–10, 18, 105–6
Struve, Peter 45
Tamburrano, Guiseppe 62
Terracini, Umberto 115, 152
Thalheimer, August 110–11, 130, 137–8
Therborn, Göran 68
Thomas, Peter 11–14, 16
Thompson, Edward 32
Timpanaro, Sebastiano 20
Togliatti, Palmiro 10–11, 13, 152–5
Tosin, Bruno 169–70
Trotsky, Leon 36, 38, 43, 48–9, 62, 89–90, 94,
113–14, 132, 136–41, 146, 148
Tukhachevsky, Mikhail 137–8
Tulli, Enrico 164, 169
Turati, Filippo 129
Vacca, Giuseppe 10, 154
Voltaire 9
Weber, Max 71
Weygand, Maxime 35
Wittgenstein, Ludwig 10
|